Stoic logic
Stoic logic is the system of propositional logic developed by the Stoic philosophers in ancient Greece.
It was one of the two great systems of logic in the classical world. It was largely built and shaped by Chrysippus, the third head of the Stoic school in the 3rd-century BCE. Chrysippus's logic differed from Aristotle's term logic because it was based on the analysis of propositions rather than terms. The smallest unit in Stoic logic is an assertible (the Stoic equivalent of a proposition) which is the content of a statement such as "it is day". Assertibles have a truth-value such that they are only true or false depending on when it was expressed (e.g. the assertible "it is night" will only be true if it is true that it is night).[1] In contrast, Aristotelian propositions strongly affirm or deny a predicate of a subject and seek to have its truth validated or falsified independent of context. Compound assertibles can be built up from simple ones through the use of logical connectives. The resulting syllogistic was grounded on five basic indemonstrable arguments to which all other syllogisms were claimed to be reducible.[2] The linguistic orientation of Stoic logic made it difficult for its students even within the Stoic school.[3]
Towards the end of antiquity Stoic logic was neglected in favour of Aristotle's logic, and as a result the Stoic writings on logic did not survive, and the only accounts of it were incomplete reports by other writers. Knowledge about Stoic logic as a system was lost until the 20th century, when logicians familiar with the modern propositional calculus reappraised the ancient accounts of it.
Background
[edit]Stoicism is a school of philosophy which developed in the Hellenistic period around a generation after the time of Aristotle.[4] The Stoics believed that the universe operated according to reason, i.e. by a God which is immersed in nature itself.[4] Logic (logike) was the part of philosophy which examined reason (logos).[5] To achieve a happy life—a life worth living—requires logical thought.[4] The Stoics held that an understanding of ethics was impossible without logic.[6] In the words of Inwood, the Stoics believed that:[7]
Logic helps a person see what is the case, reason effectively about practical affairs, stand his or her ground amid confusion, differentiate the certain from the probable, and so forth.
Aristotle's term logic can be viewed as a logic of classification.[8] It makes use of four logical terms "all", "some", "is/are", and "is/are not" and to that extent is fairly static.[8][9] The Stoics needed a logic that examines choice and consequence.[6] The Stoics therefore developed a logic of propositions which uses connectives such as "if ... then", "either ... or", and "not both".[10] Such connectives are part of everyday reasoning.[10] Socrates in the Dialogues of Plato often asks a fellow citizen if they believe a certain thing; when they agree, Socrates then proceeds to show how the consequences are logically false or absurd, inferring that the original belief must be wrong.[10] Similar attempts at forensic reasoning must have been used in the law-courts, and they are a fundamental part of Greek mathematics.[10] Aristotle himself was familiar with propositions, and his pupils Theophrastus and Eudemus had examined hypothetical syllogisms, but there was no attempt by the Peripatetic school to develop these ideas into a system of logic.[11]
The Stoic tradition of logic originated in the 4th-century BCE in a different school of philosophy known as the Megarian school.[12] It was two dialecticians of this school, Diodorus Cronus and his pupil Philo, who developed their own theories of modalities and of conditional propositions.[12] The founder of Stoicism, Zeno of Citium, studied under the Megarians and he was said to have been a fellow pupil with Philo.[13] However, the outstanding figure in the development of Stoic logic was Chrysippus of Soli (c. 279 – c. 206 BCE), the third head of the Stoic school.[12] Chrysippus shaped much of Stoic logic as we know it creating a system of propositional logic.[14] As a logician Chrysippus is sometimes said to rival Aristotle in stature.[13] The logical writings by Chrysippus are, however, almost entirely lost,[12] instead his system has to be reconstructed from the partial and incomplete accounts preserved in the works of later authors such as Sextus Empiricus, Diogenes Laërtius, and Galen.[13]
Propositions
[edit]To the Stoics, logic was a wide field of knowledge which included the study of language, grammar, rhetoric and epistemology.[5] However, all of these fields were interrelated, and the Stoics developed their logic (or "dialectic") within the context of their theory of language and epistemology.[15]
Assertibles
[edit]The Stoics held that any meaningful utterance will involve three items: the sounds uttered; the thing which is referred to or described by the utterance; and an incorporeal item—the lektón (sayable)—that which is conveyed in the language.[16] The lekton is not a statement but the content of a statement, and it corresponds to a complete utterance.[17][18] A lekton can be something such as a question or a command, but Stoic logic operates on those lekta which are called "assertibles" (axiomata), described as a proposition which is either true or false and which affirms or denies.[17][19] Examples of assertibles include "it is night", "it is raining this afternoon", and "no one is walking."[20][21] The assertibles are truth-bearers.[22] They can never be true and false at the same time (law of noncontradiction) and they must be at least true or false (law of excluded middle).[23] The Stoics catalogued these simple assertibles according to whether they are affirmative or negative, and whether they are definite or indefinite (or both).[24] The assertibles are much like modern propositions, however their truth value can change depending on when they are asserted.[1] Thus an assertible such as "it is night" will only be true when it is night and not when it is day.[19]
Compound assertibles
[edit]Simple assertibles can be connected to each other to form compound or non-simple assertibles.[25] This is achieved through the use of logical connectives.[25] Chrysippus seems to have been responsible for introducing the three main types of connectives: the conditional (if), conjunctive (and), and disjunctive (or).[26] A typical conditional takes the form of "if p then q";[27] whereas a conjunction takes the form of "both p and q";[27] and a disjunction takes the form of "either p or q".[28] The or they used is exclusive, unlike the inclusive or generally used in modern formal logic.[29] These connectives are combined with the use of not for negation.[30] Thus the conditional can take the following four forms:[31]
- If p, then q | If not p, then q | If p, then not q | If not p, then not q
Later Stoics added more connectives: the pseudo-conditional took the form of "since p then q"; and the causal assertible took the form of "because p then q".[a] There was also a comparative (or dissertive): "more/less (likely) p than q".[32]
Logical connectives | ||
---|---|---|
Name | Type | Example |
Conditional | if | if it is day, it is light |
Conjunction | and | it is day and light |
Disjunction | either ... or | either it is day or night |
Pseudo-conditional | since | since it is day, it is light |
Causal | because | because it is day, it is light |
Comparative | more/less likely ... than | more likely it is day than night |
Modality
[edit]Assertibles can also be distinguished by their modal properties[b]—whether they are possible, impossible, necessary, or non-necessary.[33] In this the Stoics were building on an earlier Megarian debate initiated by Diodorus Cronus.[33] Diodorus had defined possibility in a way which seemed to adopt a form of fatalism.[34] Diodorus defined possible as "that which either is or will be true".[35] Thus there are no possibilities that are forever unrealised, whatever is possible is or one day will be true.[34] His pupil Philo, rejecting this, defined possible as "that which is capable of being true by the proposition's own nature",[35] thus a statement like "this piece of wood can burn" is possible, even if it spent its entire existence on the bottom of the ocean.[36] Chrysippus, on the other hand, was a causal determinist: he thought that true causes inevitably give rise to their effects and that all things arise in this way.[37] But he was not a logical determinist or fatalist: he wanted to distinguish between possible and necessary truths.[37] Thus he took a middle position between Diodorus and Philo, combining elements of both their modal systems.[38] Chrysippus's set of Stoic modal definitions was as follows:[39]
Modal definitions | ||
---|---|---|
Name | Definition | |
possible | An assertible which can become true and is not hindered by external things from becoming true | |
impossible | An assertible which cannot become true or which can become true but is hindered by external things from becoming true | |
necessary | An assertible which (when true) cannot become false or which can become false but is hindered by external things from becoming false | |
non-necessary | An assertible which can become false and is not hindered by external things from becoming false |
Syllogistic
[edit]Arguments
[edit]In Stoic logic, an argument (λόγος) is defined as a compound or system of premisses (λήμματα) and a conclusion (ἐπιφορά, συμπέρασμα).[40][41] A typical Stoic syllogism is:
- If it is day, it is light;
- It is day;
- Therefore it is light.[41]
It has a non-simple assertible for the first premise ("If it is day, it is light") and a simple assertible for the second premise ("It is day").[41] The second premise doesn't always have to be simple but it will have fewer components than the first.[41]
In more formal terms this type of syllogism is:[19]
- If p, then q;
- p;
- Therefore q.
As with Aristotle's term logic, Stoic logic also uses variables, but the values of the variables are propositions not terms.[42] Chrysippus listed five basic argument forms, which he regarded as true beyond dispute.[43][44] [c] These five indemonstrable arguments are made up of conditional, disjunction, and negation conjunction connectives,[45] and all other arguments are reducible to these five indemonstrable arguments.[18][46]
Indemonstrable arguments | |||
---|---|---|---|
Name[d] | Description | Modern sequent | Example |
Modus ponens | If p, then q. p. Therefore, q. | If it is day, it is light. It is day. Therefore, it is light. | |
Modus tollens | If p, then q. Not q. Therefore, not p. | If it is day, it is light. It is not light. Therefore, it is not day. | |
Modus ponendo tollens | Not both p and q. p. Therefore, not q. | It is not both day and night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night. | |
Strong modus tollendo ponens | Either p or q. Not p. Therefore, q. | It is either day or night. It is not day. Therefore, it is night. | |
Strong modus ponendo tollens | Either p or q. p. Therefore, not q. | It is either day or night. It is day. Therefore, it is not night. |
There can be many variations of these five indemonstrable arguments.[47] For example the assertibles in the premises can be more complex, and the following syllogism is a valid example of the second indemonstrable (modus tollens):[31]
- if both p and q, then r;
- not r;
- therefore not: both p and q
Similarly one can incorporate negation into these arguments.[31] A valid example of the fourth indemonstrable (strong modus tollendo ponens or exclusive disjunctive syllogism) is:[48]
- either [not p] or q;
- not [not p];
- therefore q
which, incorporating the principle of double negation, is equivalent to:[48]
- either [not p] or q;
- p;
- therefore q
Analysis
[edit]Many arguments are not in the form of the five indemonstrables, and the task is to show how they can be reduced to one of the five types.[30] A simple example of Stoic reduction is reported by Sextus Empiricus:[49]
- if both p and q, then r;
- not r;
- but also p;
- Therefore not q
This can be reduced to two separate indemonstrable arguments of the second and third type:[50]
- if both p and q, then r;
- not r;
- therefore not: both p and q
- not: both p and q
- p;
- therefore not q
The Stoics stated that complex syllogisms could be reduced to the indemonstrables through the use of four ground rules or themata.[51][52] Of these four themata, only two have survived.[53][35] One, the so-called first thema, was a rule of antilogism:[35]
When from two [assertibles] a third follows, then from either of them together with the contradictory of the conclusion the contradictory of the other follows (Apuleius, De Interpretatione 209. 9–14).
In modern sequent: .
The other, the third thema, was a cut rule by which chain syllogisms could be reduced to simple syllogisms.[e] The importance of these rules is not altogether clear.[54] In the 2nd-century BCE Antipater of Tarsus is said to have introduced a simpler method involving the use of fewer themata, although few details survive concerning this.[54] In any case, the themata cannot have been a necessary part of every analysis.[55]
Paradoxes
[edit]Why should not the philosopher develop his own reason? You turn to vessels of crystal, I to the syllogism called The Liar; you to myrrhine glassware, I to the syllogism called The Denyer.
–Epictetus, Discourses, iii.9.20
In addition to describing which inferences are valid ones, part of a Stoic's logical training was the enumeration and refutation of false arguments, including the identification of paradoxes.[56] A false argument could be one with a false premise or which is formally incorrect, however paradoxes represented a challenge to the basic logical notions of the Stoics such as truth or falsehood.[57] One famous paradox, known as The Liar, asked "A man says he is lying; is what he says true or false?"—if the man says something true then it seems he is lying, but if he is lying then he is not saying something true, and so on.[58] Chrysippus is known to have written several books on this paradox, although it is not known what solution he offered for it.[59] Another paradox known as the Sorites or "Heap" asked "How many grains of wheat do you need before you get a heap?"[59] It was said to challenge the idea of true or false by offering up the possibility of vagueness.[59] The response of Chrysippus however was: "That doesn't harm me, for like a skilled driver I shall restrain my horses before I reach the edge ... In like manner I restrain myself in advance and stop replying to sophistical questions."[59]
However, this mastery of logical puzzles, study of paradoxes, and dissection of arguments[60] was not an end in itself, but rather its purpose was for the Stoics to cultivate their rational powers.[61] Stoic logic was thus a method of self-discovery.[62] Its aim was to enable ethical reflection, permit secure and confident arguing, and lead the pupil to truth.[60] The end result would be thought that is consistent, clear and precise, and which exposes confusion, murkiness and inconsistency.[63] Diogenes Laërtius gives a list of dialectical virtues, which were probably invented by Chrysippus:[64]
First he mentions aproptosia, which means literally 'not falling forward' and is defined as 'knowledge of when one should give assent or not' (give assent); next aneikaiotes, 'unhastiness', defined as 'strong-mindedness against the probable (or plausible), so as not to give in to it'; third, anelenxia, 'irrefutability', the definition of which is 'strength in argument, so as not to be driven by it to the contradictory'; and fourth, amataiotes, 'lack of emptyheadedness', defined as 'a disposition which refers impressions (phantasiai) to the correct logos.[64]
Later reception
[edit]For around five hundred years Stoic logic was one of the two great systems of logic.[65] The logic of Chrysippus was discussed alongside that of Aristotle, and it may well have been more prominent since Stoicism was the dominant philosophical school.[66] From a modern perspective Aristotle's term logic and the Stoic logic of propositions appear complementary, but they were sometimes regarded as rival systems.[30] In late antiquity the Stoic school fell into decline, and the last pagan philosophical school, the Neoplatonists, adopted Aristotle's logic for their own.[67] Only elements of Stoic logic made their way into the logical writings of later commentators such as Boethius, transmitting confused parts of Stoic logic to the Middle Ages.[66] Propositional logic was redeveloped by Peter Abelard in the 12th-century, but by the mid-15th-century the only logic which was being studied was a simplified version of Aristotle's.[68]
In the 18th-century Immanuel Kant declared that "since Aristotle ... logic has not been able to advance a single step, and is thus to all appearance a closed and complete body of doctrine."[69] To 19th-century historians, who believed that Hellenistic philosophy represented a decline from that of Plato and Aristotle, Stoic logic was seen with contempt.[70] Carl Prantl thought that Stoic logic was "dullness, triviality, and scholastic quibbling" and he welcomed the fact that the works of Chrysippus were no longer extant.[71] Eduard Zeller remarked that "the whole contribution of the Stoics to the field of logic consists in their having clothed the logic of the Peripatetics with a new terminology."[72]
Although developments in modern logic that parallel Stoic logic[73] began in the middle of the 19th-century with the work of George Boole and Augustus De Morgan,[68] Stoic logic itself was only reappraised in the 20th-century,[71] beginning with the work of Polish logician Jan Łukasiewicz[71] and Benson Mates.[71]
What we see as a result is a close similarity between [these] methods of reasoning and the behaviour of digital computers. ... The code happens to come from the nineteenth-century logician and mathematician George Boole, whose aim was to codify the relations studied much earlier by Chrysippus (albeit with greater abstraction and sophistication). Later generations built on Boole's insights ... but the logic that made it all possible was the interconnected logic of an interconnected universe, discovered by the ancient Chrysippus, who labored long ago under an old Athenian stoa.[74]
Notes
[edit]a. ^ The minimum requirement for a conditional is that the consequent follows from the antecedent.[27] The pseudo-conditional adds that the antecedent must also be true. The causal assertible adds an asymmetry rule such that if p is the cause/reason for q, then q cannot be the cause/reason for p. Bobzien 1999, p. 109
b. ^ "Stoic modal logic is not a logic of modal propositions (e.g., propositions of the type 'It is possible that it is day' ...) ... instead, their modal theory was about non-modalized propositions like 'It is day', insofar as they are possible, necessary, and so forth." Bobzien 1999, p. 117
c. ^ Most of these argument forms had already been discussed by Theophrastus, but: "It is plain that even if Theophrastus discussed (1)–(5), he did not anticipate Chrysippus' achievement. ... his Aristotelian approach to the study and organization of argument-forms would have given his discussion of mixed hypothetical syllogisms an utterly unStoical aspect." Barnes 1999, p. 83
d. ^ These Latin names date from the Middle Ages. Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 288
e. ^ For a brief summary of these themata see Susanne Bobzien's Ancient Logic article for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. For a detailed (and technical) analysis of the themata, including a tentative reconstruction of the two lost ones, see Bobzien 1999, pp. 137–148, Long & Sedley 1987, §36 HIJ.
Citations
[edit]- ^ Jump up to: a b Bobzien 1999, p. 95
- ^ Ian Mueller (1978) An Introduction to Stoic Logic Rist 1978, pp. 2–13
- ^ Luhtala 2000, p. 64
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 74
- ^ Jump up to: a b Sellars 2006, p. 55
- ^ Jump up to: a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 78
- ^ Inwood 2003, p. 229
- ^ Jump up to: a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 73
- ^ Sellars 2006, p. 57
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 79
- ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 507
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d Bobzien 1996a, p. 880
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Sellars 2006, p. 56
- ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 80
- ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 400
- ^ Everson 1994, p. 85
- ^ Jump up to: a b Johansen & Rosenmeier 1998, p. 466
- ^ Jump up to: a b Ierodiakonou 2006, p. 678
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Sellars 2006, p. 58
- ^ Sellars 2006, pp. 58–59
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 102
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 92
- ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 88
- ^ Bobzien 1999, pp. 97–98
- ^ Jump up to: a b Bobzien 1999, p. 103
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 105
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Bobzien 1999, p. 106
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 109
- ^ Inwood 2003, p. 231
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Sellars 2006, p. 60
- ^ Jump up to: a b c Bobzien 1999, p. 129
- ^ Bobzien 1999, pp. 109–111
- ^ Jump up to: a b Sellars 2006, p. 59
- ^ Jump up to: a b Adamson 2015, p. 136
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d Bobzien 2020
- ^ Adamson 2015, p. 138
- ^ Jump up to: a b Adamson 2015, p. 58
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 120
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 118
- ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 45,76
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d Bobzien 1999, p. 121
- ^ Bobzien 1996a, p. 881
- ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 79-81
- ^ Mates 1953, pp. 67–73
- ^ Asmus & Restall2012, p. 21
- ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 78
- ^ Bobzien 1999, p. 128
- ^ Jump up to: a b Shenefelt & White 2013, p. 87
- ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 521
- ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 522
- ^ Bochenski 1961, pp. 126–130
- ^ Bobzien 1996b, p. 133
- ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 169
- ^ Jump up to: a b Barnes 1997, p. 82
- ^ Barnes 1997, p. 83
- ^ Inwood 2003, p. 232
- ^ Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 525
- ^ Asmus & Restall 2012, p. 20
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d Ierodiakonou 2009, p. 526
- ^ Jump up to: a b Nussbaum 2009, p. 349
- ^ Long 2001, p. 95
- ^ Long 2001, p. 102
- ^ Nussbaum 2009, pp. 348–349
- ^ Jump up to: a b Long 2001, p. 92 citing Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 46f.
- ^ Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 113
- ^ Jump up to: a b Kneale & Kneale 1962, p. 177
- ^ Sharples 2003, p. 156
- ^ Jump up to: a b Hurley 2011, p. 6
- ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 403 quoting Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.
- ^ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 403
- ^ Jump up to: a b c d O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 397
- ^ Zeller 1880, p. 124
- ^ Bonevac & Dever 2012, p. 181
- ^ Shenefelt & White 2013, pp. 96–97
References
[edit]- Adamson, Peter (2015), Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3
- Asmus, Conrad; Restall, Greg (2012), "A History of the Consequence Relations", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Woods, John (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 2, Elsevier, ISBN 978-0-444-52937-4
- Barnes, Johnathan (1997), Logic and the Imperial Stoa, Brill, ISBN 90-04-10828-9
- Barnes, Johnathan (1999), "Logic: The Peripatetics", in Algra, Keimpe (ed.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-25028-5
- Bobzien, Susanne (1996a), "Logic", in Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony (eds.), The Oxford Classical Dictionary, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-1986-6172-6
- Bobzien, Susanne (1996b), "Stoic Syllogistic", Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 14, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-1982-3670-2
- Bobzien, Susanne (1999), "Logic: The Stoics", in Algra, Keimpe (ed.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-25028-5
- Bobzien, Susanne (2020). "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Bochenski, Benson (1961), A history of formal logic, University of Notre Dame Press
- Bonevac, Daniel; Dever, Josh (2012), "A History of the Connectives", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Woods, John (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 2, Elsevier, ISBN 978-0-444-52937-4
- Everson, Stephen (1994), Companions to Ancient Thought 3: Language, Cambridge University Press
- Hadot, Pierre (2002), What is Ancient Philosophy?, Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-00733-6
- Hurley, Patrick J. (2011), A Concise Introduction to Logic, Wadsworth, ISBN 978-0-8400-3417-5
- Ierodiakonou, Katerina (2006), "Stoicism", in Wilson, Nigel (ed.), Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece, Psychology Press, ISBN 978-0-4158-7396-3
- Ierodiakonou, Katerina (2009), "Stoic Logic", in Gill, Mary Louise; Pellegrin, Pierre (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Wiley-Blackwell, ISBN 978-1-4051-8834-0
- Inwood, Brad (2003), "Stoicism", in Furley, David (ed.), Routledge History of Philosophy Volume II: Aristotle to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 978-0-4153-0874-8
- Johansen, Karsten Friis; Rosenmeier, Henrik (1998), A History of Ancient Philosophy: From the Beginnings to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 0-415-12738-6
- Kenny, Anthony (2006), Ancient Philosophy, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-875272-1
- Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1962), The Development of Logic, Clarendon Press
- Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:7. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- Long, A. A.; Sedley, D. N., eds. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge University Press.
- Long, A. A. (2001), "Dialectic and the Stoic Sage", Stoic Studies, University of California Press, ISBN 0-520-22974-6
- Luhtala, Anneli (2000), On the Origin of Syntactical Description in Stoic Logic, Nodus Publikationen, ISBN 3893234578
- Mates, Benson (1953), Stoic Logic, University of California Press
- Nussbaum, Martha C. (2009), The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics, Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0-691-14131-2
- O'Toole, Robert R.; Jennings, Raymond E. (2004), "The Megarians and the Stoics", in Gabbay, Dov M.; Woods, John (eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 1, Elsevier, ISBN 0-444-51596-8
- Rist, John M., ed. (1978). The Stoics. University of California Press. ISBN 0-520-03135-0.
- Sellars, John (2006), Ancient Philosophies: Stoicism, Acumen, ISBN 978-1-84465-053-8
- Shenefelt, Michael; White, Heidi (2013), If A, Then B: How Logic Shaped the World, Columbia University Press, ISBN 978-0-231-53519-9
- Sharples, Robert W. (2003), "The Peripatetic School", in Furley, David (ed.), Routledge History of Philosophy Volume II: Aristotle to Augustine, Routledge, ISBN 978-0-4153-0874-8
- Zeller, Eduard (1880), The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Longmans, Green, and Co.
External links
[edit]- Bobzien, Susanne. "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Stoic Logic (1953) by Benson Mates (1919–2009)