Jump to content

Crispin Wright

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Superassertibility)

Crispin Wright
Born (1942-12-21) 21 December 1942 (age 81)
Alma materTrinity College, Cambridge
Era20th-century philosophy
21st-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic
Neo-logicism (Scottish School)[1]
InstitutionsAll Souls College, Oxford
Main interests
Philosophy of mind
Philosophy of language
Philosophy of mathematics
Frege · Wittgenstein
Epistemology
Notable ideas
Rule-following considerations[2]
Neo-logicism
Truth pluralism[3]
Epistemic entitlement[4]
Superassertibility
Anti-realist semantics for empirical language[5]
Warrant transmission failure[6]
Cornerstone proposition[4]

Crispin James Garth Wright (/rt/; born 21 December 1942) is a British philosopher, who has written on neo-Fregean (neo-logicist) philosophy of mathematics, Wittgenstein's later philosophy, and on issues related to truth, realism, cognitivism, skepticism, knowledge, and objectivity. He is Professor of Philosophical Research at the University of Stirling, and taught previously at the University of St Andrews, University of Aberdeen, New York University, Princeton University and University of Michigan.[7]

Life and career

[edit]

Wright was born in Surrey and was educated at Birkenhead School (1950–61) and at Trinity College, Cambridge, graduating in Moral Sciences in 1964 and taking a PhD in 1968. He took an Oxford BPhil in 1969 and was elected Prize Fellow and then Research Fellow at All Souls College, Oxford, where he worked until 1978. He then moved to the University of St. Andrews, where he was appointed Professor of Logic and Metaphysics and then the first Bishop Wardlaw University Professorship in 1997.[8] From fall 2008 to spring 2023, he was professor in the Department of Philosophy at New York University (NYU). He has also taught at the University of Michigan, Oxford University, Columbia University, and Princeton University. Crispin Wright was founder and director of Arché at the University of St. Andrews,[9] which he left in September 2009 to take up leadership of the Northern Institute of Philosophy (NIP) at the University of Aberdeen. Once NIP ceased operations in 2015,[10] Wright moved to the University of Stirling.

Philosophical work

[edit]

In the philosophy of mathematics, he is best known for his book Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects (1983), where he argues that Frege's logicist project could be revived by removing the axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension (sometimes referred to as Basic Law V) from the formal system. Arithmetic is then derivable in second-order logic from Hume's principle. He gives informal arguments that (i) Hume's principle plus second-order logic is consistent, and (ii) from it one can produce the Dedekind–Peano axioms.[11] Both results were proven informally by Gottlob Frege (Frege's Theorem), and would later be more rigorously proven by George Boolos and Richard Heck. Wright is one of the major proponents of neo-logicism, alongside his frequent collaborator Bob Hale. He has also written Wittgenstein and the Foundations of Mathematics (1980).

In general metaphysics, his most important work is Truth and Objectivity (Harvard University Press, 1992). He argues in this book that there need be no single, discourse-invariant thing in which truth consists, making an analogy with identity. There need only be some principles regarding how the truth predicate can be applied to a sentence, some 'platitudes' about true sentences. Wright also argues that in some contexts, probably including moral contexts, superassertibility will effectively function as a truth predicate. He defines a predicate as superassertible if and only if it is "assertible" in some state of information and then remains so no matter how that state of information is enlarged upon or improved. Assertiveness is warrant by whatever standards inform the discourse in question.[12] Many of his most important papers in philosophy of language, epistemology, philosophical logic, meta-ethics, and the interpretation of Wittgenstein have been collected in the two volumes published by Harvard University Press in 2001 and 2003.

In epistemology, Wright has argued that G. E. Moore's proof of an external world ("Here is one hand") is logically valid but cannot transmit warrant from its premise to the conclusion, as it instantiates a form of epistemic circularity called by him "warrant transmission failure".[13] Wright has also developed a variant of Ludwig Wittgenstein's hinge epistemology, introduced in Wittgenstein's On Certainty as a response to radical skepticism. According to hinge epistemology, there are assumptions or presuppositions of any enquiry – called "hinge propositions" – that cannot themselves be rationally doubted, challenged, established or defended. Wright contends that certain hinge propositions can actually be rationally held because there exists a type of non-evidential, a priori warrant – which Wright calls "epistemic entitlement" – for accepting them as true.[14]

Awards

[edit]

Books

[edit]
  • Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics (Harvard University Press, 1980)
  • Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects (Humanities Press 1983)
  • Truth and Objectivity (Harvard University Press, 1992)
  • Realism, Meaning, and Truth, 2nd edition (Blackwell 1993)
  • The Reason's Proper Study (co-authored with Bob Hale) (Oxford University Press, 2001)
  • Rails to Infinity (Harvard University Press, 2001)
  • Saving the Differences (Harvard University Press, 2003).

References

[edit]
  1. ^ st-andrews.ac.uk Archived 2006-12-24 at the Wayback Machine
  2. ^ C. Wright (1989), "Wittgenstein's Rule-following Considerations and the Central Project of Theoretical Linguistics", in Reflections on Chomsky, ed. A. George, Oxford and New York: Basil Blackwell; reprinted in C. Wright (2001), Rails to Infinity, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard.
  3. ^ Pluralist Theories of Truth (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  4. ^ a b >Epistemic Entitlement – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  5. ^ Dummett, Michael – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  6. ^ Transmission of Justification and Warrant - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  7. ^ "Career". 27 September 2017. Archived from the original on 19 February 2020. Retrieved 19 February 2020.[unreliable source?]
  8. ^ C. Wright (2009). "Foreword: on becoming a philosopher," Synthese, 171: 359–364.
  9. ^ C. Wright (2009). "Foreword: on becoming a philosopher," Synthese, 171: 359–364.
  10. ^ "crispinjwright.com". 27 September 2017. Archived from the original on 19 February 2020. Retrieved 19 February 2020.
  11. ^ G. Currie (1985). "Crispin Wright [1983]: Frege's Conception of Number as Objects. Scots Philosophical Monographs, no. 2, Aberdeen University Press. xxi+193 pp. Hardback £12.50. Paperback £8.50". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36:4, 475-479.
  12. ^ M. R. Sainsbury (1996). "Crispin Wright: Truth and Objectivity". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. 56, No. 4, pp. 899-904 .
  13. ^ C. Wright (2002). "(Anti-)Sceptics Simple and Subtle: G. E. Moore and John McDowell," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65: 330–348.
  14. ^ C. Wright (2004). "Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free?)," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 78: 167–212.
  15. ^ "amacad.org" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 9 December 2016. Retrieved 24 July 2016.
  16. ^ britac.ac.uk
[edit]