Jump to content

Logica nova

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In the history of logic, the term logica nova (Latin, meaning "new logic") refers to a subdivision of the logical tradition of Western Europe, as it existed around the middle of the twelfth century. The Logica vetus ("old logic") referred to works of Aristotle that had long been known and studied in the Latin West, whereas the Logica nova referred to forms of logic derived from Aristotle's works which had been unavailable until they were translated by James of Venice in the 12th century. Study of the Logica nova was part of the Renaissance of the 12th century.

Overview

[edit]

The division of works was as follows:[1]

These works, excluding the Liber sex principiorum, were already canonical in the time of Abelard.[4] He wrote his so-called Logica Ingredientibus on the scheme of a set of seven commentaries.

The advent of the logica nova was the result of new Latin translations, particularly by James of Venice. The combination of the two logics was termed the logica antiquorum (logic of the ancients). Restricting just to the works of Aristotle, the whole Organon of six works was split by the historical accidents of transmission into two books in the logica vetus, and four in the logica nova.

Some of the religious orders organized special studia for the formation of their members dedicated to the study of the new logic. For example, after the theology component of the studium provinciale of the Dominican Order at the Roman convent of Santa Sabina was transferred in 1288 to the convent of Santa Maria sopra Minerva,[5]: 323  which would develop into the College of Saint Thomas in the 15th century and into the Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Angelicum, the Santa Sabina studium was redesignated in 1291 as one of three studia nove logice of the Order. These studia were intended to offer courses of advanced logic covering the logica nova, the Aristotelian texts recovered in the West only in the second half of the 12th century, the Topics, Sophistical Refutations, and the First and Second Analytics of Aristotle. This was an advance over the logica antiqua, which treated the Isagoge of Porphyry, Divisions and Topics of Boethius, the Categories and On Interpretation of Aristotle, and the Summule logicales of Peter of Spain.[5]: 236–237  Milone da Velletri was lector there in 1293[6] In 1310 the Florentine Giovanni dei Tornaquinci was lector there.[7] In 1331 Nerius de Tertia was lector,[8] and Giovanni Zocco da Spoleto was a student of logic there.[9]

Another usage for logica nova is for the later theories of Ramón Lull. The logica parva refers to an important textbook of Paul of Venice.

The terminology had some currency at least until the seventeenth century, and Johannes Clauberg's Logica vetus et nova (1654).

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ "CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Logic".
  2. ^ "The Cambridge Companion to Abelard - Cambridge University Press".
  3. ^ See Medieval Philosophy for a more detailed list of relevant commentaries by Boethius.
  4. ^ PDF, p. 8. Archived September 11, 2006, at the Wayback Machine
  5. ^ Jump up to: a b Marian Michèle Mulchahey (1998). "First the bow is bent in study": Dominican education before 1350. PIMS. ISBN 9780888441324.
  6. ^ "1302-1303". e-theca.net. Retrieved 2012-04-06.
  7. ^ "1311". e-theca.net. Retrieved 2012-04-05.
  8. ^ "(2006) CrOv". e-theca.net. Retrieved 2012-04-05.
  9. ^ "⌂ 5. Le tribolazioni degli spoletini [→ Spoleto]". e-theca.net. Retrieved 2011-07-05.