Jump to content

Friedrich Hayek

(Redirected from Freidrich Hayek)

Friedrich Hayek
Born
Friedrich August von Hayek

(1899-05-08)8 May 1899
Died23 March 1992(1992-03-23) (aged 92)
Freiburg im Breisgau, Baden-Württemberg, Germany
Resting placeNeustifter Friedhof [de], Vienna, Austria
CitizenshipAustrian (1899–1938)
British (1938–1992)[1]
Education
Spouses
Helen Berta Maria von Fritsch
(m. 1926, divorced)
Helene Bitterlich
(m. 1950)
ChildrenChristine Maria Felicitas von Hayek (daughter)[2]
Laurence Hayek (son)[3] plus 2 step-sons
Parent(s)August von Hayek (father)
Felicitas von Juraschek (mother)
Relatives
Academic career
Field
Institution
School or
tradition
Austrian School
Influences
Contributions
Awards
Information at IDEAS / RePEc
Signature

Friedrich August von Hayek CH FBA (/ˈhək/ HY-ək, German: [ˈfʁiːdʁɪç ˈʔaʊɡʊst fɔn ˈhaɪɛk] ; 8 May 1899 – 23 March 1992), often referred to by his initials F. A. Hayek, was an Austrian-British academic, who contributed to economics, political philosophy, psychology, and intellectual history.[4][5][6][7] Hayek shared the 1974 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences with Gunnar Myrdal for work on money and economic fluctuations, and the interdependence of economic, social and institutional phenomena.[8] His account of how prices communicate information is widely regarded as an important contribution to economics that led to him receiving the prize.[9][10][11]

During his teenage years, Hayek fought in World War I. He later said this experience, coupled with his desire to help avoid the mistakes that led to the war, drew him into economics.[12][13] He earned doctoral degrees in law in 1921 and political science in 1923 from the University of Vienna.[12][14] He subsequently lived and worked in Austria, Great Britain, the United States, and Germany. He became a British citizen in 1938.[15] His academic life was mostly spent at the London School of Economics, later at the University of Chicago, and the University of Freiburg. He is widely considered a major contributor to the Austrian School of Economics.[16][17]

Hayek had considerable influence on a variety of political movements of the 20th century, and his ideas continue to influence thinkers from a variety of political backgrounds today.[18][19][20] Although sometimes described as a conservative,[21] Hayek himself was uncomfortable with this label and preferred to be thought of as a classical liberal.[22][23] As the co-founder of the Mont Pelerin Society he contributed to the revival of classical liberalism in the post-war era.[24] His most popular work, The Road to Serfdom, has been republished many times over the eight decades since its original publication; General Motors created a popular cartoon version.[25][26]

Hayek was appointed a Member of the Order of the Companions of Honour in 1984 for his academic contributions to economics.[27][28] He was the first recipient of the Hanns Martin Schleyer Prize in 1984.[29] He also received the Presidential Medal of Freedom in 1991 from President George H. W. Bush.[30] In 2011, his article "The Use of Knowledge in Society" was selected as one of the top 20 articles published in the American Economic Review during its first 100 years.[31]

Life

[edit]

Early life

[edit]

Friedrich August von Hayek was born in Vienna to August von Hayek and Felicitas Hayek (née von Juraschek). Both of his parents had Czech family surnames and Czech ancestry.[32][33] The surname Hayek is the Germanized spelling of the Czech surname Hájek.[28] Hayek traced his paternal Czech ancestry to an ancestor with the surname "Hagek" who came from Prague in the 1500s.[34]

His father, born in 1871, also in Vienna, was a medical doctor employed by the municipal ministry of health.[35] August was a part-time botany lecturer at the University of Vienna.[8] Friedrich was the oldest of three brothers, Heinrich (1900–1969) and Erich (1904–1986), who were one-and-a-half and five years younger than he was.[36]

His father's career as a university professor influenced Hayek's goals later in life.[37] Both of his grandfathers, who lived long enough for Hayek to know them, were scholars.[38] Franz von Juraschek was a leading economist in Austria-Hungary and a close friend of Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, one of the founders of the Austrian School of Economics.[39] Hayek's paternal grandfather, Gustav Edler von Hayek, taught natural sciences at the Imperial Realobergymnasium (secondary school) in Vienna. He wrote works in the field of biological systematics, some of which are relatively well known.[40]

On his mother's side, Hayek was second cousin to the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein.[41] His mother often played with Wittgenstein's sisters and had known him well. As a result of their family relationship, Hayek became one of the first to read Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus when the book was published in its original German edition in 1921.[42] Although he met Wittgenstein on only a few occasions, Hayek said that Wittgenstein's philosophy and methods of analysis had a profound influence on his own life and thought.[43] In his later years, Hayek recalled a discussion of philosophy with Wittgenstein when both were officers during World War I.[44] After Wittgenstein's death, Hayek had intended to write a biography of Wittgenstein and worked on collecting family materials and later assisted biographers of Wittgenstein.[45] He was related to Wittgenstein on the non-Jewish side of the Wittgenstein family. Since his youth, Hayek frequently socialized with Jewish intellectuals, and he mentions that people often speculated whether he was also of Jewish ancestry. That made him curious, so he spent some time researching his ancestors and found out that he had no Jewish ancestors within five generations.[46]

Hayek displayed an intellectual and academic bent from a very young age and read fluently and frequently before going to school.[15][47] However, he did quite poorly at school, due to the lack of interest and problems with teachers.[48] He was at the bottom of his class in most subjects and once received three failing grades, in Latin, Greek, and mathematics.[48] He was very interested in theater, even attempting to write some tragedies, and biology, regularly helping his father with his botanical work.[49] At his father's suggestion, as a teenager he read the genetic and evolutionary works of Hugo de Vries and August Weismann and the philosophical works of Ludwig Feuerbach.[50] He noted Goethe as the greatest early intellectual influence.[49] In school, Hayek was much taken by one instructor's lectures on Aristotle's ethics.[51] In his unpublished autobiographical notes, Hayek recalled a division between him and his younger brothers who were only a few years younger than him, but he believed that they were somehow of a different generation. He preferred to associate with adults.[47]

In 1917, Hayek joined an artillery regiment in the Austro-Hungarian Army and fought on the Italian front.[52] Hayek suffered damage to his hearing in his left ear during the war[53] and was decorated for bravery.

Hayek then decided to pursue an academic career, determined to help avoid the mistakes that had led to the war. Hayek said of his experience: "The decisive influence was really World War I. It's bound to draw your attention to the problems of political organization". He vowed to work for a better world.[54]

Education

[edit]

At the University of Vienna, Hayek initially studied mostly philosophy, psychology and economics.[17] The university allowed students to choose their subjects freely and there was not much obligatory written work, or tests except main exams at the end of the study.[55] By the end of his studies Hayek became more interested in economics, mostly for financial and career reasons; he planned to combine law and economics to start a career in diplomatic service.[56] He earned doctorates in law and political science in 1921 and 1923 respectively.[17]

For a short time, when the University of Vienna closed he studied in Constantin von Monakow's Institute of Brain Anatomy, where Hayek spent much of his time staining brain cells.[57] Hayek's time in Monakow's lab and his deep interest in the work of Ernst Mach inspired his first intellectual project, eventually published as The Sensory Order (1952).[58][57] It located connective learning at the physical and neurological levels, rejecting the "sense data" associationism of the empiricists and logical positivists.[58] Hayek presented his work to the private seminar he had created with Herbert Furth called the Geistkreis.[59]

During Hayek's years at the University of Vienna, Carl Menger's work on the explanatory strategy of social science and Friedrich von Wieser's commanding presence in the classroom left a lasting influence on him.[50] Upon the completion of his examinations, Hayek was hired by Ludwig von Mises on the recommendation of Wieser as a specialist for the Austrian government working on the legal and economic details of the Treaty of Saint-Germain-en-Laye.[60] Between 1923 and 1924, Hayek worked as a research assistant to Professor Jeremiah Jenks of New York University, compiling macroeconomic data on the American economy and the operations of the Federal Reserve.[61] He was influenced by Wesley Clair Mitchell and started a doctoral program on problems of monetary stabilization but didn't finish it.[62] His time in America wasn't especially happy. He had very limited social contacts, missed the cultural life of Vienna, and was troubled by his poverty.[63] His family's financial situation deteriorated significantly after the War.[64]

Initially sympathetic to Wieser's democratic socialism, Hayek found Marxism rigid and unattractive, and his mild socialist phase lasted until he was about 23.[65] Hayek's economic thinking shifted away from socialism and toward the classical liberalism of Carl Menger after reading von Mises' book Socialism.[60] It was sometime after reading Socialism that Hayek began attending von Mises' private seminars, joining several of his university friends, including Fritz Machlup, Alfred Schutz, Felix Kaufmann and Gottfried Haberler, who were also participating in Hayek's own more general and private seminar. It was during this time that he also encountered and befriended noted political philosopher Eric Voegelin, with whom he retained a long-standing relationship.[66]

London School of Economics

[edit]

With the help of Mises, in the late 1920s, he founded and served as director of the Austrian Institute for Business Cycle Research before joining the faculty of the London School of Economics (LSE) in 1931 at the behest of Lionel Robbins.[67] Upon his arrival in London, Hayek was quickly recognised as one of the leading economic theorists in the world and his development of the economics of processes in time and the co-ordination function of prices inspired the ground-breaking work of John Hicks, Abba P. Lerner and many others in the development of modern microeconomics.[68]

In 1932, Hayek suggested that private investment in the public markets was a better road to wealth and economic co-ordination in Britain than government spending programs as argued in an exchange of letters with John Maynard Keynes, co-signed with Lionel Robbins and others in The Times.[69][70] The nearly decade long deflationary depression in Britain dating from Winston Churchill's decision in 1925 to return Britain to the gold standard at the old pre-war and pre-inflationary par was the public policy backdrop for Hayek's dissenting engagement with Keynes over British monetary and fiscal policy.[71] Keynes called Hayek's book Prices and Production "one of the most frightful muddles I have ever read", famously adding: "It is an extraordinary example of how, starting with a mistake, a remorseless logician can end in Bedlam".[72]

Notable economists who studied with Hayek at the LSE in the 1930s and 1940s include Arthur Lewis, Ronald Coase, William Baumol, CH Douglas, John Kenneth Galbraith, Leonid Hurwicz, Abba Lerner, Nicholas Kaldor, George Shackle, Thomas Balogh, L. K. Jha, Arthur Seldon, Paul Rosenstein-Rodan and Oskar Lange.[73][74][35] Some were supportive and some were critical of his ideas. Hayek also taught or tutored many other LSE students, including David Rockefeller.[75]

Unwilling to return to Austria after the Anschluss brought it under the control of Nazi Germany in 1938, Hayek remained in Britain. Hayek and his children became British subjects in 1938.[76] He held this status for the remainder of his life, but he did not live in Great Britain after 1950. He lived in the United States from 1950 to 1962 and then mostly in Germany, but also briefly in Austria.[77]

In 1947, Hayek was elected a Fellow of the Econometric Society.[78]

The Road to Serfdom

[edit]

Hayek was concerned about the general view in Britain's academia that fascism was a capitalist reaction to socialism and The Road to Serfdom arose from those concerns.[79] The title was inspired by the French classical liberal thinker Alexis de Tocqueville's writings on the "road to servitude".[80] It was first published in Britain by Routledge in March 1944 and was quite popular, leading Hayek to call it "that unobtainable book" also due in part to wartime paper rationing.[81] When it was published in the United States by the University of Chicago in September of that year, it achieved greater popularity than in Britain.[82] At the instigation of editor Max Eastman, the American magazine Reader's Digest also published an abridged version in April 1945, enabling The Road to Serfdom to reach a far wider audience than academics. The book is widely popular among those advocating individualism and classical liberalism.[83]

Chicago

[edit]

In 1950, Hayek left the London School of Economics. After spending the 1949–1950 academic year as a visiting professor at the University of Arkansas, Hayek was conferred professorship by the University of Chicago, where he became a professor in the Committee on Social Thought.[84] Hayek's salary was funded not by the university, but by an outside foundation, the William Volker Fund.[85]

Hayek had made contact with many at the University of Chicago in the 1940s, with Hayek's The Road to Serfdom playing a seminal role in transforming how Milton Friedman and others understood how society works.[86] Hayek conducted a number of influential faculty seminars while at the University of Chicago and a number of academics worked on research projects sympathetic to some of Hayek's own, such as Aaron Director, who was active in the Chicago School in helping to fund and establish what became the "Law and Society" program in the University of Chicago Law School.[87] Hayek, Frank Knight, Friedman and George Stigler worked together in forming the Mont Pèlerin Society, an international forum for neoliberals.[88] Hayek and Friedman cooperated in support of the Intercollegiate Society of Individualists, later renamed the Intercollegiate Studies Institute, an American student organisation devoted to libertarian ideas.[77][89]

Although they shared most political beliefs, disagreeing primarily on the question of monetary policy,[90] Hayek and Friedman worked in separate university departments with different research interests and never developed a close working relationship.[91] According to Alan O. Ebenstein, who wrote biographies of both of them, Hayek probably had a closer friendship with Keynes than with Friedman.[92]

Hayek received a Guggenheim Fellowship in 1954.[93][94]

Another influential political philosopher and German-speaking exile at the University of Chicago at the time was Leo Strauss, but according to his student Joseph Cropsey who also knew Hayek, there was no contact between the two of them.[95]

After editing a book on John Stuart Mill's letters he planned to publish two books on the liberal order, The Constitution of Liberty and "The Creative Powers of a Free Civilization" (eventually the title for the second chapter of The Constitution of Liberty).[96] He completed The Constitution of Liberty in May 1959, with publication in February 1960. Hayek was concerned that "with that condition of men in which coercion of some by others is reduced as much as is possible in society".[97] Hayek was disappointed that the book did not receive the same enthusiastic general reception as The Road to Serfdom had sixteen years before.[98]

He left Chicago mostly because of financial reasons, being concerned about his pension provisions.[99] His primary source of income was his salary, and he received some additional money from book royalties but avoided other lucrative sources of income for academics such as writing textbooks.[100] He spent a lot on his frequent travels. [100] He regularly spent summers in Austrian Alps, usually in the Tyrolean village Obergurgl where he enjoyed mountain climbing, and also visited Japan four times with additional trips to Tahiti, Fiji, Indonesia, Australia, New Caledonia and Ceylon.[101] After his divorce, his financial situation worsened.[102]

Freiburg and Salzburg

[edit]

From 1962 until his retirement in 1968, he was a professor at the University of Freiburg, West Germany, where he began work on his next book, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Hayek regarded his years at Freiburg as "very fruitful".[103] Following his retirement, Hayek spent a year as a visiting professor of philosophy at the University of California, Los Angeles, where he continued work on Law, Legislation and Liberty, teaching a graduate seminar by the same name and another on the philosophy of social science.[64] Preliminary drafts of the book were completed by 1970, but Hayek chose to rework his drafts and finally brought the book to publication in three volumes in 1973, 1976 and 1979.[104]

Hayek became a professor at the University of Salzburg from 1969 to 1977 and then returned to Freiburg.[15] When Hayek left Salzburg in 1977, he wrote: "I made a mistake in moving to Salzburg". The economics department was small, and the library facilities were inadequate.[105]

Although Hayek's health suffered, and he fell into a depressionary bout, he continued to work on his magnum opus, Law, Legislation and Liberty in periods when he was feeling better.[106]

Nobel Memorial Prize

[edit]

On 9 October 1974, it was announced that Hayek would be awarded the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics with Swedish economist Gunnar Myrdal, with the reasons for selection being listed in a press release.[107] He was surprised at being given the award and believed that he was given it with Myrdal to balance the award with someone from the opposite side of the political spectrum.[108] The Sveriges-Riksbank Nobel Prize in Economics was established in 1968, and Hayek was the first non-Keynesian economist to win it.

Among the reasons given, the committee stated, Hayek "was one of the few economists who gave warning of the possibility of a major economic crisis before the great crash came in the autumn of 1929."[107] The following year, Hayek further confirmed his original prediction. An interviewer asked, "We understand that you were one of the only economists to forecast that America was headed for a depression, is that true?" Hayek responded, "Yes."[109] However, no textual evidence has emerged of "a prediction".[110][111] Indeed, Hayek wrote on 26 October 1929, three days before the crash, "at present there is no reason to expect a sudden crash of the New York stock exchange. ... The credit possibilities/conditions are, at any rate, currently very great, and therefore it appears assured that an outright crisis-like destruction of the present high [price] level should not be feared."[112][113]

During the Nobel ceremony in December 1974, Hayek met the Russian dissident Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn.[114] Hayek later sent him a Russian translation of The Road to Serfdom.[108] He spoke with apprehension at his award speech about the danger the authority of the prize would lend to an economist,[115] but the prize brought much greater public awareness to the then controversial ideas of Hayek and was described by his biographer as "the great rejuvenating event in his life".[116]

British politics

[edit]

In February 1975, Margaret Thatcher was elected leader of the British Conservative Party. The Institute of Economic Affairs arranged a meeting between Hayek and Thatcher in London soon after.[117] During Thatcher's only visit to the Conservative Research Department in the summer of 1975, a speaker had prepared a paper on why the "middle way" was the pragmatic path the Conservative Party should take, avoiding the extremes of left and right. Before he had finished, Thatcher "reached into her briefcase and took out a book. It was Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty. Interrupting our pragmatist, she held the book up for all of us to see. 'This', she said sternly, 'is what we believe', and banged Hayek down on the table".[118]

Despite the media depictions of him as Thatcher's guru and power behind the throne, the communication between him and the Prime Minister was not very regular, they were in contact only once or twice a year.[119] Besides Thatcher, Hayek also made a significant influence on Enoch Powell, Keith Joseph, Nigel Lawson, Geoffrey Howe and John Biffen.[120]

Hayek gained some controversy in 1978 by praising Thatcher's anti-immigration policy proposal in an article which ignited numerous accusations of anti-Semitism and racism because of his reflections on the inability of assimilation of Eastern European Jews in the Vienna of his youth.[120] He defended himself by explaining that he made no racial judgements, only highlighted the problems of acculturation.[121]

In 1977, Hayek was critical of the Lib–Lab pact in which the British Liberal Party agreed to keep the British Labour government in office. Writing to The Times, Hayek said: "May one who has devoted a large part of his life to the study of the history and the principles of liberalism point out that a party that keeps a socialist government in power has lost all title to the name 'Liberal'. Certainly no liberal can in future vote 'Liberal'".[122] Hayek was criticised by Liberal politicians Gladwyn Jebb and Andrew Phillips, who both claimed that the purpose of the pact was to discourage socialist legislation.

Lord Gladwyn pointed out that the German Free Democrats were in coalition with the German Social Democrats.[123] Hayek was defended by Professor Antony Flew, who stated that—unlike the British Labour Party—the German Social Democrats had since the late 1950s abandoned public ownership of the means of production, distribution and exchange and had instead embraced the social market economy.[124]

In 1978, Hayek came into conflict with Liberal Party leader David Steel, who claimed that liberty was possible only with "social justice and an equitable distribution of wealth and power, which in turn require a degree of active government intervention" and that the Conservative Party were more concerned with the connection between liberty and private enterprise than between liberty and democracy. Hayek claimed that a limited democracy might be better than other forms of limited government at protecting liberty, but that an unlimited democracy was worse than other forms of unlimited government because "its government loses the power even to do what it thinks right if any group on which its majority depends thinks otherwise".

Hayek stated that if the Conservative leader had said "that free choice is to be exercised more in the market place than in the ballot box, she has merely uttered the truism that the first is indispensable for individual freedom while the second is not: free choice can at least exist under a dictatorship that can limit itself but not under the government of an unlimited democracy which cannot".[125]

Hayek supported Britain in the Falklands War, writing that it would be justified to attack Argentinian territory instead of just defending the islands, which earned him a lot of criticism in Argentina, a country which he also visited several times. He was also displeased by the weak response of the United States to the Iran hostage crisis, claiming that an ultimatum should be issued and Iran bombed if they do not comply. He supported Ronald Reagan's decision to keep high defence spending, believing that a strong US military is a guarantee of world peace and necessary to keep the Soviet Union under control.[126] President Reagan listed Hayek as among the two or three people who most influenced his philosophy and welcomed him to the White House as a special guest.[127] Senator Barry Goldwater listed Hayek as his favourite political philosopher and congressman Jack Kemp named him an inspiration for his political career.[128]

Recognition

[edit]

In 1980, Hayek was one of twelve Nobel laureates to meet with Pope John Paul II "to dialogue, discuss views in their fields, communicate regarding the relationship between Catholicism and science, and 'bring to the Pontiff's attention the problems which the Nobel Prize Winners, in their respective fields of study, consider to be the most urgent for contemporary man'"[129]

Hayek was appointed a Member of the Order of the Companions of Honour (CH) in the 1984 Birthday Honours by Elizabeth II on the advice of British Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher for his "services to the study of economics".[27][28] Hayek had hoped to receive a baronetcy and after being awarded the CH sent a letter to his friends requesting that he be called the English version of Friedrich (i.e. Frederick) from now on. After his twenty-minute audience with the Queen, he was "absolutely besotted" with her according to his daughter-in-law Esca Hayek. Hayek said a year later that he was "amazed by her. That ease and skill, as if she'd known me all my life". The audience with the Queen was followed by a dinner with family and friends at the Institute of Economic Affairs. When later that evening Hayek was dropped off at the Reform Club, he commented: "I've just had the happiest day of my life".[28]

In 1991, President George H. W. Bush awarded Hayek the Presidential Medal of Freedom, one of the two highest civilian awards in the United States, for a "lifetime of looking beyond the horizon".[130]

Death

[edit]

Hayek died on 23 March 1992, aged 92, in Freiburg, Germany and was buried on 4 April in the Neustift am Walde cemetery in the northern outskirts of Vienna according to the Catholic rite.[131] In 2011, his article "The Use of Knowledge in Society" was selected as one of the top 20 articles published in The American Economic Review during its first 100 years.[31]

The New York University Journal of Law and Liberty holds an annual lecture in his honor.[132]

Work and views

[edit]

Business cycle

[edit]
Parts of a business cycle
Parts of a business cycle
Actual business cycle
Actual business cycle

Ludwig von Mises had earlier applied the concept of marginal utility to the value of money in his Theory of Money and Credit (1912) in which he also proposed an explanation for "industrial fluctuations" based on the ideas of the old British Currency School and of Swedish economist Knut Wicksell.[133] Hayek used this body of work as a starting point for his own interpretation of the business cycle, elaborating what later became known as the Austrian theory of the business cycle.[134] Hayek spelled out the Austrian approach in more detail in his book, published in 1929, an English translation of which appeared in 1933 as Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle. There, Hayek argued for a monetary approach to the origins of the cycle. In his Prices and Production (1931), Hayek argued that the business cycle resulted from the central bank's inflationary credit expansion and its transmission over time, leading to a capital misallocation caused by the artificially low interest rates.[135] Hayek claimed that "the past instability of the market economy is the consequence of the exclusion of the most important regulator of the market mechanism, money, from itself being regulated by the market process".[136]

Hayek's analysis was based on Eugen Böhm von Bawerk's concept of the "average period of production" and on the effects that monetary policy could have upon it.[137] In accordance with the reasoning later outlined in his essay "The Use of Knowledge in Society" (1945), Hayek argued that a monopolistic governmental agency like a central bank can neither possess the relevant information which should govern supply of money, nor have the ability to use it correctly.[138]

In 1929, Lionel Robbins assumed the helm of the London School of Economics (LSE).[67] Eager to promote alternatives to what he regarded as the narrow approach of the school of economic thought that then dominated the English-speaking academic world (centered at the University of Cambridge and deriving largely from the work of Alfred Marshall), Robbins invited Hayek to join the faculty at LSE, which he did in 1931.[139] According to Nicholas Kaldor, Hayek's theory of the time-structure of capital and of the business cycle initially "fascinated the academic world" and appeared to offer a less "facile and superficial" understanding of macroeconomics than the Cambridge school's.[140]

Also in 1931, Hayek crititicized John Maynard Keynes's Treatise on Money (1930) in his "Reflections on the pure theory of Mr. J.M. Keynes"[141] and published his lectures at the LSE in book form as Prices and Production.[142] For Keynes, unemployment and idle resources are caused by a lack of effective demand, but for Hayek they stem from a previous unsustainable episode of easy money and artificially low interest rates.[136] Keynes asked his friend Piero Sraffa to respond. Sraffa elaborated on the effect of inflation-induced "forced savings" on the capital sector and about the definition of a "natural" interest rate in a growing economy (see Sraffa–Hayek debate).[143] Others who responded negatively to Hayek's work on the business cycle included John Hicks, Frank Knight and Gunnar Myrdal, who, later on, would share the Sveriges-Riksbank Prize in Economics with him.[144] Kaldor later wrote that Hayek's Prices and Production had produced "a remarkable crop of critics" and that the total number of pages in British and American journals dedicated to the resulting debate "could rarely have been equalled in the economic controversies of the past".[140]

Hayek's work, throughout the 1940s, was largely ignored, except for scathing critiques by Nicholas Kaldor.[140][145] Lionel Robbins himself, who had embraced the Austrian theory of the business cycle in The Great Depression (1934), later regretted having written the book and accepted many of the Keynesian counter-arguments.[146]

Hayek never produced the book-length treatment of "the dynamics of capital" that he had promised in the Pure Theory of Capital.[147] At the University of Chicago, Hayek was not part of the economics department and did not influence the rebirth of neoclassical theory that took place there (see Chicago school of economics).[84] When in 1974 he shared the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics with Myrdal, the latter complained about being paired with an "ideologue". Milton Friedman declared himself "an enormous admirer of Hayek, but not for his economics".[148] Milton Friedman also commented on some of his writings, saying "I think Prices and Production is a very flawed book. I think his [Pure Theory of Capital] is unreadable. On the other hand, The Road to Serfdom is one of the great books of our time".[146]

Economic calculation problem

[edit]

Building on the earlier work of Mises and others, Hayek also argued that while in centrally planned economies an individual or a select group of individuals must determine the distribution of resources, these planners will never have enough information to carry out this allocation reliably. This argument, first proposed by Max Weber and Ludwig von Mises, says that the efficient exchange and use of resources can be maintained only through the price mechanism in free markets (see economic calculation problem).[149]

In 1935, Hayek published Collectivist Economic Planning, a collection of essays from an earlier debate that had been initiated by Mises. Hayek included Mises's essay in which Mises argued that rational planning was impossible under socialism.[150]

Socialist Oskar Lange responded by invoking general equilibrium theory, which they argued disproved Mises's thesis. They noted that the difference between a planned and a free market system lay in who was responsible for solving the equations.[151] They argued that if some of the prices chosen by socialist managers were wrong, gluts or shortages would appear, signalling them to adjust the prices up or down, just as in a free market.[152] Through such a trial and error, a socialist economy could mimic the efficiency of a free market system while avoiding its many problems.[153]

Hayek challenged this vision in a series of contributions. In "Economics and Knowledge" (1937), he pointed out that the standard equilibrium theory assumed that all agents have full and correct information, and how, in his mind, in the real world different individuals have different bits of knowledge and furthermore some of what they believe is wrong.[154]

In "The Use of Knowledge in Society" (1945), Hayek argued that the price mechanism serves to share and synchronise local and personal knowledge, allowing society's members to achieve diverse and complicated ends through a principle of spontaneous self-organization. He contrasted the use of the price mechanism with central planning, arguing that the former allows for more rapid adaptation to changes in particular circumstances of time and place.[155] Thus, Hayek set the stage for Oliver Williamson's later contrast between markets and hierarchies as alternative co-ordination mechanisms for economic transactions.[156] He used the term catallaxy to describe a "self-organizing system of voluntary co-operation". Hayek's research into this argument was specifically cited by the Nobel Committee in its press release awarding Hayek the Nobel prize.[107]

Investment and choice

[edit]

Hayek made breakthroughs in the choice theory, and examined the inter-relations between non-permanent production goods and "latent" or potentially economic permanent resources, building on the choice theoretical insight that "processes that take more time will evidently not be adopted unless they yield a greater return than those that take less time".[157]

Philosophy of science

[edit]

During World War II, Hayek began the Abuse of Reason project. His goal was to show how a number of then-popular doctrines and beliefs had a common origin in some fundamental misconceptions about the social science.[158]

Ideas were developed in The Counter-Revolution of Science in 1952 and in some of Hayek's later essays in the philosophy of science such as "Degrees of Explanation" (1955) and "The Theory of Complex Phenomena" (1964).[159]

In Counter-Revolution, for example, Hayek observed that the hard sciences attempt to remove the "human factor" to obtain objective and strictly controlled results:

[T]he persistent effort of modern Science has been to get down to "objective facts," to cease studying what men thought about nature or regarding the given concepts as true images of the real world, and, above all, to discard all theories which pretended to explain phenomena by imputing to them a directing mind like our own. Instead, its main task became to revise and reconstruct the concepts formed from ordinary experience on the basis of a systematic testing of the phenomena, so as to be better able to recognize the particular as an instance of a general rule.

— Friedrich Hayek, The Counter-Revolution of Science (Chapter II, "The Problem and the Method of the Natural Sciences")

Meanwhile, the soft sciences are attempting to measure human action itself:

The social sciences in the narrower sense, i.e., those which used to be described as the moral sciences, are concerned with man's conscious or reflected action, actions where a person can be said to choose between various courses open to him, and here the situation is essentially different. The external stimulus which may be said to cause or occasion such actions can of course also be defined in purely physical terms. But if we tried to do so for the purposes of explaining human action, we would confine ourselves to less than we know about the situation.

— Friedrich Hayek, The Counter-Revolution of Science (Chapter III, "The Subjective Character of the Data of the Social Sciences")

He notes that these are mutually exclusive and that social sciences should not attempt to impose positivist methodology, nor to claim objective or definite results:[160]

Psychology

[edit]

Hayek's first academic essay was a psychological work titled 'Contributions to the Theory of the Development of Consciousness' (Beiträge zur Theorie der Entwicklung des Bewußtseins) In The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology (1952), Hayek independently developed a "Hebbian learning" model of learning and memory—an idea he first conceived in 1920 prior to his study of economics. Hayek's expansion of the "Hebbian synapse" construction into a global brain theory received attention in neuroscience, cognitive science, computer science, and evolutionary psychology by scientists such as Gerald Edelman, Vittorio Guidano and Joaquin Fuster.[161][162][163]

The Sensory Order can be viewed as a development of his attack on scientism. Hayek posited two orders, namely the sensory order that we experience and the natural order that natural science revealed. Hayek thought that the sensory order actually is a product of the brain. He described the brain as a very complex yet self-ordering hierarchical classification system, a huge network of connections. Because of the nature of the classifier system, richness of our sensory experience can exist. Hayek's description posed problems to behaviorism, whose proponents took the sensory order as fundamental.[158]

International Relations

[edit]

Hayek was a lifelong federalist. He joined several pan-European and pro-federalist movements throughout his career, and called for federal ties between the U.K. and Europe, and between Europe and the United States. After the 1950s, when the Cold War began in earnest, Hayek largely kept his federalist proposals out of the public sphere, although he did propose to federate Jerusalem as late as the 1970s.[164]

Hayek argued that closer economic ties without closer political ties would lead to more problems because interest groups in nation-states would best be able to counter the internationalization of markets that comes with closer economic ties by appealing to nationalism.[165] Much of his time in the pro-federalist and pan-European groups was spent arguing with pro-federal and pan-European democratic socialists over the proper extent of a world federal government. Hayek argued that such a world government should do little more than act as a negative check on national sovereignties and serve as a focal point for collective defense.[166]

As the Cold War heated up, Hayek grew more hawkish and he pushed his federal proposals onto the backburner in favor of more traditional public policy proposals that acknowledged and respected the sovereignty of nation-states.[167] Yet Hayek never disavowed his famous call for "the abrogation of national sovereignties"[168] and his lifetime of work in the area of international relations continues to attract attention from scholars searching for federalist answers to contemporary problems in international relations.[169][170][171][172]

Social and political philosophy

[edit]

Two traditions in the theory of liberty

[edit]

In the latter half of his career, Hayek made a number of contributions to social and political philosophy which he based on his views on the limits of human knowledge and the idea of spontaneous order in social institutions. He argues in favour of a society organised around a market order in which the apparatus of state is employed almost (though not entirely) exclusively to enforce the legal order (consisting of abstract rules and not particular commands) necessary for a market of free individuals to function. These ideas were informed by a moral philosophy derived from epistemological concerns regarding the inherent limits of human knowledge. Hayek argued that his ideal individualistic and free-market polity would be self-regulating to such a degree that it would be "a society which does not depend for its functioning on our finding good men for running it".[173]

He discusses the contrasting traditions of liberty—British and French—in the theory of freedom. The British tradition, influenced by thinkers like David Hume and Adam Smith, emphasizes the organic growth of institutions and the spontaneous evolution of society. It recognizes that political order arises from the cumulative experience and success of individuals, rather than from deliberate design. In contrast, the French tradition, rooted in Cartesian rationalism, seeks to construct a utopia based on a belief in the unlimited powers of human reason. The French tradition, that Hayek called constructivist rationalism, gained influence over time, partly due to its assumptions about human ambition and pride. However, according to Hayek, the British tradition, with its emphasis on the gradual development of civilization and the role of individual freedom, provides a more valid theory of liberty.[173][174][175]

Spontaneous order

[edit]

Hayek viewed the free price system not as a conscious invention (that which is intentionally designed by man), but as spontaneous order or what Scottish philosopher Adam Ferguson referred to as "the result of human action but not of human design".[176] For instance, Hayek put the price mechanism on the same level as language, which he developed in his price signal theory.[177]

Hayek attributed the birth of civilisation to private property in his book The Fatal Conceit (1988).[178] He explained that price signals are the only means of enabling each economic decision maker to communicate tacit knowledge or dispersed knowledge to each other to solve the economic calculation problem.[178] Alain de Benoist of the Nouvelle Droite (New Right) produced a highly critical essay on Hayek's work in an issue of Telos, citing the flawed assumptions behind Hayek's idea of "spontaneous order" and the authoritarian and totalising implications of his free-market ideology.[179]

Hayek's concept of the market as a spontaneous order has been applied to ecosystems to defend a broadly non-interventionist policy.[180] Like the market, ecosystems contain complex networks of information, involve an ongoing dynamic process, contain orders within orders and the entire system operates without being directed by a conscious mind.[181] On this analysis, species takes the place of price as a visible element of the system formed by a complex set of largely unknowable elements. Human ignorance about the countless interactions between the organisms of an ecosystem limits our ability to manipulate nature.[182]

Hayek's price signal concept is in relation to how consumers are often unaware of specific events that change market, yet change their decisions, simply because the price goes up. Thus pricing communicates information.[183]

Criticism of collectivism

[edit]

Hayek was one of the leading academic critics of collectivism in the 20th century.[15] In Hayek's view, the central role of the state should be to maintain the rule of law, with as little arbitrary intervention as possible.[97] In his popular book The Road to Serfdom (1944) and in subsequent academic works, Hayek argued that socialism required central economic planning and that such planning in turn leads towards totalitarianism.[184]

In The Road to Serfdom, Hayek wrote:

Although our modern socialists' promise of greater freedom is genuine and sincere, in recent years observer after observer has been impressed by the unforeseen consequences of socialism, the extraordinary similarity in many respects of the conditions under "communism" and "fascism".[185]

Hayek posited that a central planning authority would have to be endowed with powers that would impact and ultimately control social life because the knowledge required for centrally planning an economy is inherently decentralised, and would need to be brought under control.[150]

Though Hayek did argue that the state should provide law centrally, others have pointed out that this contradicts his arguments about the role of judges in "discovering" the law, suggesting that Hayek would have supported decentralized provision of legal services.[186]

Hayek also wrote that the state can play a role in the economy, specifically in creating a safety net, saying:

There is no reason why, in a society which has reached the general level of wealth ours has, the first kind of security should not be guaranteed to all without endangering general freedom; that is: some minimum of food, shelter and clothing, sufficient to preserve health. Nor is there any reason why the state should not help to organize a comprehensive system of social insurance in providing for those common hazards of life against which few can make adequate provision.[187]

"The Denationalization of Money" is one of his literary works, in which he advocated the establishment of competitions in issuing moneys.[188]

Social safety nets

[edit]

With regard to a social safety net, Hayek advocated "some provision for those threatened by the extremes of indigence or starvation due to circumstances beyond their control" and argued that the "necessity of some such arrangement in an industrial society is unquestioned—be it only in the interest of those who require protection against acts of desperation on the part of the needy".[189] Summarizing Hayek's views on the topic, journalist Nicholas Wapshott has argued that "[Hayek] advocated mandatory universal health care and unemployment insurance, enforced, if not directly provided, by the state".[190] Critical theorist Bernard Harcourt has argued further that "Hayek was adamant about this".[191] In 1944, Hayek wrote in The Road to Serfdom:

There is no reason why in a society which has reached the general level of wealth which ours has attained [that security against severe physical privation, the certainty of a given minimum of sustenance for all; or more briefly, the security of a minimum income] should not be guaranteed to all without endangering general freedom. There are difficult questions about the precise standard which should thus be assured... but there can be no doubt that some minimum of food, shelter, and clothing, sufficient to preserve health and the capacity to work, can be assured to everybody. Indeed, for a considerable part of the population of England this sort of security has long been achieved.
Nor is there any reason why the state should not assist... individuals in providing for those common hazards of life against which, because of their uncertainty, few individuals can make adequate provision. Where, as in the case of sickness and accident, neither the desire to avoid such calamities nor the efforts to overcome their consequences are as a rule weakened by the provision of assistance—where, in short, we deal with genuinely insurable risks—the case for the state's helping to organize a comprehensive system of social insurance is very strong. There are many points of detail where those wishing to preserve the competitive system and those wishing to supersede it by something different will disagree on the details of such schemes; and it is possible under the name of social insurance to introduce measures which tend to make competition more or less effective. But there is no incompatibility in principle between the state's providing greater security in this way and the preservation of individual freedom. Wherever communal action can mitigate disasters against which the individual can neither attempt to guard himself nor make the provision for the consequences, such communal action should undoubtedly be taken.[192]

In 1973, Hayek reiterated in Law, Legislation and Liberty:

There is no reason why in a free society government should not assure to all, protection against severe deprivation in the form of an assured minimum income, or a floor below which nobody need to descend. To enter into such an insurance against extreme misfortune may well be in the interest of all; or it may be felt to be a clear moral duty of all to assist, within the organised community, those who cannot help themselves. So long as such a uniform minimum income is provided outside the market to all those who, for any reason, are unable to earn in the market an adequate maintenance, this need not lead to a restriction of freedom, or conflict with the Rule of law.[193]

Political theorist Adam James Tebble has argued that Hayek's concession of a social minimum provided by the state introduces a conceptual tension with his epistemically derived commitment to private property rights, free markets, and spontaneous order.[194]

Criticism of "social justice"

[edit]

Although Hayek believed in a society governed by laws, he disapproved of the notion of "social justice". He compared the market to a game in which "there is no point in calling the outcome just or unjust"[195] and argued that "social justice is an empty phrase with no determinable content".[196] Likewise, "the results of the individual's efforts are necessarily unpredictable, and the question as to whether the resulting distribution of incomes is just has no meaning".[197] He generally regarded government redistribution of income or capital as an unacceptable intrusion upon individual freedom, saying that "the principle of distributive justice, once introduced, would not be fulfilled until the whole of society was organized in accordance with it. This would produce a kind of society which in all essential respects would be the opposite of a free society".[196]

Liberalism and skepticism

[edit]

Arthur M. Diamond argues Hayek's problems arise when he goes beyond claims that can be evaluated within economic science. Diamond argued:

The human mind, Hayek says, is not just limited in its ability to synthesize a vast array of concrete facts, it is also limited in its ability to give a deductively sound ground to ethics. Here is where the tension develops, for he also wants to give a reasoned moral defense of the free market. He is an intellectual skeptic who wants to give political philosophy a secure intellectual foundation. It is thus not too surprising that what results is confused and contradictory.[198]

Chandran Kukathas argues that Hayek's defence of liberalism is unsuccessful because it rests on presuppositions that are incompatible. The unresolved dilemma of his political philosophy is how to mount a systematic defence of liberalism if one emphasizes the limited capacity of reason.[199] Norman P. Barry similarly notes that the "critical rationalism" in Hayek's writings appears incompatible with "a certain kind of fatalism, that we must wait for evolution to pronounce its verdict".[200] Milton Friedman and Anna Schwartz argue that the element of paradox exists in the views of Hayek. Noting Hayek's vigorous defense of "invisible hand" evolution that Hayek claimed created better economic institutions than could be created by rational design, Friedman pointed out the irony that Hayek was then proposing to replace the monetary system thus created with a deliberate construct of his own design.[201] John N. Gray summarized this view as "his scheme for an ultra-liberal constitution was a prototypical version of the philosophy he had attacked".[202] Bruce Caldwell wrote that "[i]f one is judging his work against the standard of whether he provided a finished political philosophy, Hayek clearly did not succeed", although he thinks that "economists may find Hayek's political writings useful".[203]

Dictatorship and totalitarianism

[edit]

Hayek sent António de Oliveira Salazar a copy of The Constitution of Liberty (1960) in 1962. Hayek hoped that his book—this "preliminary sketch of new constitutional principles"—"may assist" Salazar "in his endeavour to design a constitution which is proof against the abuses of democracy".[204]

Hayek visited Chile in the 1970s and 1980s during the Government Junta of general Augusto Pinochet and accepted being appointed Honorary Chairman of the Centro de Estudios Públicos, the think tank formed by the economists who transformed Chile into a free market economy.[204]

Asked about the military dictatorship of Chile by a Chilean interviewer, Hayek is translated from German to Spanish to English as having said the following:

As long term institutions, I am totally against dictatorships. But a dictatorship may be a necessary system for a transitional period. [...] Personally I prefer a liberal dictatorship to democratic government devoid of liberalism. My personal impression—and this is valid for South America—is that in Chile, for example, we will witness a transition from a dictatorial government to a liberal government.[104]

In a letter to the London Times, he defended the Pinochet regime and said that he had "not been able to find a single person even in much maligned Chile who did not agree that personal freedom was much greater under Pinochet than it had been under Allende".[205][206] Hayek admitted that "it is not very likely that this will succeed, even if, at a particular point in time, it may be the only hope there is", but he explained that "[i]t is not certain hope, because it will always depend on the goodwill of an individual, and there are very few individuals one can trust. But if it is the sole opportunity which exists at a particular moment it may be the best solution despite this. And only if and when the dictatorial government is visibly directing its steps towards limited democracy".

For Hayek, the distinction between authoritarianism and totalitarianism has much importance and he was at pains to emphasise his opposition to totalitarianism, noting that the concept of transitional dictatorship which he defended was characterised by authoritarianism, not totalitarianism. For example, when Hayek visited Venezuela in May 1981, he was asked to comment on the prevalence of totalitarian regimes in Latin America. In reply, Hayek warned against confusing "totalitarianism with authoritarianism" and said that he was unaware of "any totalitarian governments in Latin America. The only one was Chile under Allende". For Hayek, the word "totalitarian" signifies something very specific, namely the intention to "organize the whole of society" to attain a "definite social goal" which is stark in contrast to "liberalism and individualism".[207] He claimed that democracy can also be repressive and totalitarian; in The Constitution of Liberty he often refers to Jacob Talmon's concept of totalitarian democracy.

Immigration, nationalism and race

[edit]

Hayek was skeptical about international immigration and supported Thatcher's anti-immigration policies.[120] In Law, Legislation and Liberty he elaborated:

Freedom of migration is one of the widely accepted and wholly admirable principles of liberalism. But should this generally give the stranger a right to settle down in a community in which he is not welcome? Has he a claim to be given a job or be sold a house if no resident is willing to do so? He clearly should be entitled to accept a job or buy a house if offered to him. But have the individual inhabitants a duty to offer either to him? Or ought it to be an offence if they voluntarily agree not to do so? Swiss and Tyrolese villages have a way of keeping out strangers which neither infringe nor rely on any law. Is this anti-liberal or morally justified? For established old communities I have no certain answers to these questions.[208]

He was mainly preoccupied with practical problems concerning immigration:

There exist, of course, other reasons why such restrictions appear unavoidable so long as certain differences in national or ethnic traditions (especially differences in the rate of propagation) exist-which in turn are not likely to disappear so long as restrictions on migration continue. We must face the fact that we here encounter a limit to the universal application of those liberal principles of policy which the existing facts of the present world make unavoidable.[209]

He was not sympathetic to nationalist ideas and was afraid that mass immigration might revive nationalist sentiment among domestic population and ruin the postwar progress that was made among Western nations.[210] He additionally explained:

However far modern man accepts in principle the ideal that the same rules should apply to all men, in fact he does concede it only to those whom he regards as similar to himself, and only slowly learns to extend the range of those he does accept as his likes. There is little legislation can do to speed up this process and much it may do to reverse it by re-awakening sentiments that are already on the wane.[210]

Despite his opposition to nationalism, Hayek made numerous controversial and inflammatory comments about specific ethnic groups. Answering an interview question about people he cannot deal with he mentioned his dislike of Middle Eastern populations, claiming they were dishonest, and also expressed "profound dislike" of Indian students at London School of Economics, saying that were usually "detestable sons of Bengali moneylenders".[211] He maintained that such attitudes were not based on any racial feeling.[211] During World War II he discussed the possibility of sending his children to the United States but was concerned that they might be placed with a "coloured family".[212] In a later interview, questioned about his attitude towards Black people, he said laconically that he "did not like dancing Negroes"[213] and on another occasion he ridiculed the decision to award the Nobel Peace Prize to Martin Luther King Jr.[214] He also made negative comments about awarding the Prize to Ralph Bunche, Albert Luthuli, and his LSE colleague W. Arthur Lewis who he described as an "unusually able West Indian negro".[214] In 1978 Hayek made a month-long visit to South Africa (his third) where he gave numerous lectures, interviews, and met prominent politicians and business leaders, unconcerned about possible propagandistic effect of his tour for Apartheid regime. He expressed his opposition to some of the government policies, believing that publicly funded institutions should treat all citizens equally, but also claimed that private institutions have the right to discriminate. Additionally, he condemned the "scandalous" hostility and interference of the international community in South African internal affairs.[215] He further explained his attitude:

People in South Africa have to deal with their own problems, and the idea that you can use external pressure to change people, who after all have built up a civilization of a kind, seems to me morally a very doubtful belief.[216]

While Hayek gave somewhat ambiguous comments on the injustices of Apartheid and proper role of the state, some of his Mont Pelerin colleagues, such as John Davenport and Wilhelm Röpke, were more ardent supporters of South African government and criticized Hayek for being too soft on the subject.[217]

Inequality and class

[edit]

Hayek claimed that the idea that "all men are born equal" is untrue because evolution and genetic differences have created "boundless variety of human nature". He emphasized the importance of nature, complaining that it became too fashionable to ascribe all human differences to environment.[218] Hayek defended economic inequality, believing that the existence of wealthy class is important not only for economic reasons—accumulating capital and directing investments—but also for political, cultural, scientific and conservationist goals which are often financed and promoted by philanthropists. Since the market mechanism cannot provide for all societal needs, some of which are outside of economic calculation, existence of wealthy individuals guarantees the efficiency and pluralism in their development and realization, which could not be guaranteed in the case of state monopoly.[219] Individual wealth offers independence and can create intellectual, moral, political and artistic leaders which are not employed and influenced by the state.[220] According to Hayek the society benefits from having a hereditary wealthy class because individuals born in it don't have to devote their energy to earning a living and can devote themselves to other purposes such as experimenting with different ideas, hobbies and lifestyles which can later be adopted by broader society.[221] In The Constitution of Liberty he wrote:

Yet is it really so obvious that the tennis or golf professional is a more useful member of society than the wealthy amateurs who devoted their time to perfecting these games? Or that the paid curator of a public museum is more useful than a private collector? Before the reader answers these questions too hastily, I would ask him to consider whether there would ever have been golf or tennis professionals or museum curators if wealthy amateurs had not preceded them. Can we not hope that other new interests will still arise from the playful explorations of those who can indulge in them for the short span of a human life? It is only natural that the development of the art of living and of the non-materialistic values should have profited most from the activities of those who had no material worries.[222]

He contrasted individuals who inherited wealth, with upper class values and education, with the nouveau riche who often use their wealth in more vulgar ways.[221] He decried the disappearance of such leisured aristocratic class, claiming that contemporary Western elites are usually business groups that lack intellectual leadership and coherent "philosophy of life" and use their wealth mostly for economic purposes.[223]

Hayek was against high taxes on inheritance, believing that it is natural function of the family to transmit standards, traditions and material goods. Without transmission of property, parents might try to secure the future of their children by placing them in prestigious and high-paying positions, as was customary in socialist countries, which creates even worse injustices.[224] He was also strongly against progressive taxation, noting that in most countries additional taxes paid by the rich amount to insignificantly small amount of total tax revenue and that the only major result of the policy is "gratification of the envy of the less-well-off".[225] He also claimed that it is contrary to the idea of equality under the law and against democratic principle that the majority should not impose discriminatory rules against the minority.[226][227]

Criticism

[edit]

Hayek's views on social welfare policies have also been the subject of criticism. Critics contend that his opposition to government intervention in the economy fails to recognize the need for social safety nets and other forms of support for vulnerable populations. Furthermore, it has been argued that his views on welfare policy contradict his views on social justice.[228]

Hayek's argument in The Road to Serfdom has been criticized as a slippery slope argument and therefore fallacious.[229] However, others have argued that this is a fundamental misunderstanding of the book and Hayek's point is about what central planning directly entails, not what it is likely to lead to.[230]

Influence and recognition

[edit]
An elderly Hayek in 1981

Hayek's influence on the development of economics is widely acknowledged. With regard to the popularity of his Nobel acceptance lecture, Hayek is the second-most frequently cited economist (after Kenneth Arrow) in the Nobel lectures of the prize winners in economics. Hayek wrote critically there of the field of orthodox economics and neo-classical modelisation.[231] A number of Nobel Laureates in economics, such as Vernon Smith and Herbert A. Simon, recognise Hayek as the greatest modern economist.[232] Another Nobel winner, Paul Samuelson, believed that Hayek was worthy of his award, but nevertheless claimed that "there were good historical reasons for fading memories of Hayek within the mainstream last half of the twentieth century economist fraternity. In 1931, Hayek's Prices and Production had enjoyed an ultra-short Byronic success. In retrospect hindsight tells us that its mumbo-jumbo about the period of production grossly misdiagnosed the macroeconomics of the 1927–1931 (and the 1931–2007) historical scene".[233] Despite this comment, Samuelson spent the last 50 years of his life obsessed with the problems of capital theory identified by Hayek and Böhm-Bawerk, and Samuelson flatly judged Hayek to have been right and his own teacher Joseph Schumpeter to have been wrong on the central economic question of the 20th century, the feasibility of socialist economic planning in a production goods dominated economy.[234]

Hayek is widely recognised for having introduced the time dimension to the equilibrium construction and for his key role in helping inspire the fields of growth theory, information economics and the theory of spontaneous order. The "informal" economics presented in Milton Friedman's massively influential popular work Free to Choose (1980) is explicitly Hayekian in its account of the price system as a system for transmitting and co-ordinating knowledge. This can be explained by the fact that Friedman taught Hayek's famous paper "The Use of Knowledge in Society" (1945) in his graduate seminars.

In 1944, he was elected as a Fellow of the British Academy[235] after he was nominated for membership by Keynes.[236]

Harvard economist and former Harvard University President Lawrence Summers explains Hayek's place in modern economics: "What's the single most important thing to learn from an economics course today? What I tried to leave my students with is the view that the invisible hand is more powerful than the [un]hidden hand. Things will happen in well-organized efforts without direction, controls, plans. That's the consensus among economists. That's the Hayek legacy".[237]

By 1947, Hayek was an organiser of the Mont Pelerin Society, a group of classical liberals who sought to oppose socialism. Hayek was also instrumental in the founding of the Institute of Economic Affairs, the right-wing libertarian and free-market think tank that inspired Thatcherism. He was in addition a member of the conservative and libertarian Philadelphia Society.[238]

Hayek had a long-standing and close friendship with philosopher of science Karl Popper, who was also from Vienna. In a letter to Hayek in 1944, Popper stated: "I think I have learnt more from you than from any other living thinker, except perhaps Alfred Tarski".[239] Popper dedicated his Conjectures and Refutations to Hayek. For his part, Hayek dedicated a collection of papers, Studies in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, to Popper and in 1982 said that "ever since his Logik der Forschung first came out in 1934, I have been a complete adherent to his general theory of methodology".[240] Popper also participated in the inaugural meeting of the Mont Pelerin Society. Their friendship and mutual admiration do not change the fact that there are important differences between their ideas.[241]

Hayek also played a central role in Milton Friedman's intellectual development. Friedman wrote:

My interest in public policy and political philosophy was rather casual before I joined the faculty of the University of Chicago. Informal discussions with colleagues and friends stimulated a greater interest, which was reinforced by Friedrich Hayek's powerful book The Road to Serfdom, by my attendance at the first meeting of the Mont Pelerin Society in 1947, and by discussions with Hayek after he joined the university faculty in 1950. In addition, Hayek attracted an exceptionally able group of students who were dedicated to a libertarian ideology. They started a student publication, The New Individualist Review, which was the outstanding libertarian journal of opinion for some years. I served as an adviser to the journal and published a number of articles in it....[242]

While Friedman often mentioned Hayek as an important influence, Hayek rarely mentioned Friedman.[243] He deeply disagreed with Chicago School methodology, quantitative and macroeconomic focus, and claimed that Friedman's Essays in Positive Economics was as dangerous a book as Keynes' General Theory.[244] Friedman also claimed that despite some Popperian influence Hayek always retained basic Misesian praxeological view which he found "utterly nonsensical".[245] He also noted that he admired Hayek only for his political works and disagreed with his technical economics; he called Prices and Production a "very flawed book" and The Pure Theory of Capital "unreadable". [246] There were occasional tensions at the Mont Pelerin meetings between the Hayek's and Friedman's followers that sometimes threatened to split the Society.[90] Although they worked at the same university and shared political beliefs, Hayek and Friedman rarely collaborated professionally and were not close friends.[92]

Hayek's greatest intellectual debt was to Carl Menger, who pioneered an approach to social explanation similar to that developed in Britain by Bernard Mandeville and the Scottish moral philosophers in the Scottish Enlightenment. He had a wide-reaching influence on contemporary economics, politics, philosophy, sociology, psychology and anthropology. For example, Hayek's discussion in The Road to Serfdom (1944) about truth, falsehood and the use of language influenced some later opponents of postmodernism.[247]

Some radical libertarians had a negative view of Hayek and his milder form of liberalism. Ayn Rand disliked him, seeing him as a conservative and compromiser.[248] In a letter to Rose Wilder Lane in 1946 she wrote:

Now to your question: 'Do those almost with us do more harm than 100% enemies?' I don't think this can be answered with a flat 'yes' or 'no,' because the 'almost' is such a wide term. There is one general rule to observe: those who are with us, but merely do not go far enough are the ones who may do us some good. Those who agree with us in some respects, yet preach contradictory ideas at the same time, are definitely more harmful than 100% enemies. As an example of the kind of 'almost' I would tolerate, I'd name Ludwig von Mises. As an example of our most pernicious enemy, I would name Hayek. That one is real poison.[249]

Hayek made no known written references to Rand.[250]

Wikipedia co-founder Jimmy Wales was influenced by Hayek's ideas on spontaneous order and the Austrian School of economics, after being exposed to these ideas by Austrian economist and Mises Institute Senior Fellow Mark Thornton.[251]

In the 21st century, some libertarian political scientists argue that Hayek would be in favor of Bitcoin and cryptocurrencies due to its resistance to political pressure and due to Hayek's emphasis of sound money and competition in currencies.[252] They also argue that cryptocurrency and Bitcoin serve as a "Hayekian Escape," a method that the people can use to escape the government's currency monopoly.[253]

Relation to conservatism

[edit]

Hayek received new attention in the 1980s and 1990s with the rise of conservative governments in the United States, United Kingdom and Canada. After winning the 1979 United Kingdom general election, Margaret Thatcher appointed Keith Joseph, the director of the Hayekian Centre for Policy Studies, as her secretary of state for industry in an effort to redirect parliament's economic strategies. Likewise, David Stockman, Ronald Reagan's most influential financial official in 1981, was an acknowledged follower of Hayek.[254]

Although usually identified as a conservative liberal or a liberal conservative,[255] Hayek published an essay, "Why I Am Not a Conservative" (included as an appendix to The Constitution of Liberty), in which he criticized certain aspects of conservatism from a liberal perspective. Edmund Fawcett summarizes Hayek's critique as follows:

Conservatives, on Hayek’s account, suffered from the following weaknesses. They feared change unduly. They were unreasonably frightened of uncontrolled social forces. They were too fond of authority. They had no grasp of economics. They lacked the feel for “abstraction” needed for engaging with people of different outlooks. They were too cozy with elites and establishments. They gave in to jingoism and chauvinism. They tended to think mystically, much as socialists tended to overrationalize. They were, last, too suspicious of democracy.[256]

Hayek identified himself as a classical liberal, but noted that in the United States it had become almost impossible to use "liberal" in its original definition and the term "libertarian" was used instead.[257] He also found libertarianism as a term "singularly unattractive" and offered the term "Old Whig" (a phrase borrowed from Edmund Burke) instead. In his later life, he said: "I am becoming a Burkean Whig".[258] Whiggery as a political doctrine had little affinity for classical political economy, the tabernacle of the Manchester School and William Gladstone.[259]

In his 1956 preface to The Road to Serfdom, Hayek summarized all his disagreements with conservatism in this way:

Conservatism, though a necessary element in any stable society, is not a social program; in its paternalistic, nationalistic, and poweradoring tendencies it is often closer to socialism than true liberalism; and with its traditionalistic, anti-intellectual, and often mystical propensities it will never, except in short periods of disillusionment, appeal to the young and all those others who believe that some changes are desirable if this world is to become a better place. A conservative movement, by its very nature, is bound to be a defender of established privilege and to lean on the power of government for the protection of privilege. The essence of the liberal position, however, is the denial of all privilege, if privilege is understood in its proper and original meaning of the state granting and protecting rights to some which are not available on equal terms to others.

Samuel Brittan, concluded in 2010 that "Hayek's book [The Constitution of Liberty] is still probably the most comprehensive statement of the underlying ideas of the moderate free market philosophy espoused by neoliberals".[260] Brittan adds that although Raymond Plant (2009) comes out in the end against Hayek's doctrines, Plant gives The Constitution of Liberty a "more thorough and fair-minded analysis than it has received even from its professed adherents". As a neo-liberal, he helped found the Mont Pelerin Society, a prominent neo-liberal think tank where many other minds, such as Mises and Friedman gathered.[261][260]

Although Hayek is likely a student of the neo-liberal school of libertarianism,[262] he is nonetheless influential in the conservative movement, mainly for his critique of collectivism.[26]

Policy discussions

[edit]

Hayek's ideas on spontaneous order and the importance of prices in dealing with the knowledge problem inspired a debate on economic development and transition economies after the fall of the Berlin wall. For instance, economist Peter Boettke elaborated in detail on why reforming socialism failed and the Soviet Union broke down.[263] Economist Ronald McKinnon uses Hayekian ideas to describe the challenges of transition from a centralized state and planned economy to a market economy.[264] Former World Bank Chief Economist William Easterly emphasizes why foreign aid tends to have no effect at best in books such as The White Man's Burden: Why the West's Efforts to Aid the Rest Have Done So Much Ill and So Little Good.[265]

Since the 2007–2008 financial crisis, there is a renewed interest in Hayek's core explanation of boom-and-bust cycles, which serves as an alternative explanation to that of the savings glut as launched by economist and former Federal Reserve Chair Ben Bernanke. Economists at the Bank for International Settlements, e.g. William R. White, emphasize the importance of Hayekian insights and the impact of monetary policies and credit growth as root causes of financial cycles.[266] Andreas Hoffmann and Gunther Schnabl provide an international perspective and explain recurring financial cycles in the world economy as consequence of gradual interest rate cuts led by the central banks in the large advanced economies since the 1980s.[267][268] Nicolas Cachanosky outlines the impact of American monetary policy on the production structure in Latin America.[269]

In line with Hayek, an increasing number of contemporary researchers sees expansionary monetary policies and too low interest rates as mal-incentives and main drivers of financial crises in general and the subprime market crisis in particular.[270][271] To prevent problems caused by monetary policy, Hayekian and Austrian economists discuss alternatives to current policies and organizations. For instance, Lawrence H. White argued in favor of free banking in the spirit of Hayek's "Denationalization of Money".[272] Along with market monetarist economist Scott Sumner,[273] White also noted that the monetary policy norm that Hayek prescribed, first in Prices and Production (1931) and as late as the 1970s,[274][275] was the stabilization of nominal income.[139]

Hayek's ideas find their way into the discussion of the post-Great Recession issues of secular stagnation. Monetary policy and mounting regulation are argued to have undermined the innovative forces of the market economies. Quantitative easing following the financial crises is argued to have not only conserved structural distortions in the economy, leading to a fall in trend-growth. It also created new distortions and contributes to distributional conflicts.[276]

Central European politics

[edit]

In the 1970s and 1980s, the writings of Hayek were a major influence on some of the future postsocialist economic and political elites in Central and Eastern Europe. Supporting examples include the following:

There is no figure who had more of an influence, no person had more of an influence on the intellectuals behind the Iron Curtain than Friedrich Hayek. His books were translated and published by the underground and black market editions, read widely, and undoubtedly influenced the climate of opinion that ultimately brought about the collapse of the Soviet Union.[277]

— Milton Friedman (Hoover Institution)

The most interesting among the courageous dissenters of the 1980s were the classical liberals, disciples of F.A. Hayek, from whom they had learned about the crucial importance of economic freedom and about the often-ignored conceptual difference between liberalism and democracy.[278]

— Andrzej Walicki (History, Notre Dame)

Estonian Prime Minister Mart Laar came to my office the other day to recount his country's remarkable transformation. He described a nation of people who are harder-working, more virtuous—yes, more virtuous, because the market punishes immorality—and more hopeful about the future than they've ever been in their history. I asked Mr. Laar where his government got the idea for these reforms. Do you know what he replied? He said, "We read Milton Friedman and F.A. Hayek."[279]

— United States Representative Dick Armey

I was 25 years old and pursuing my doctorate in economics when I was allowed to spend six months of post-graduate studies in Naples, Italy. I read the Western economic textbooks and also the more general work of people like Hayek. By the time I returned to Czechoslovakia, I had an understanding of the principles of the market. In 1968, I was glad at the political liberalism of the Dubcek Prague Spring, but was very critical of the Third Way they pursued in economics.[280]

— Václav Klaus (former President of the Czech Republic)

Personal life

[edit]
Hayek's grave in Neustifter Friedhof, Vienna

In August 1926, Hayek married Helen Berta Maria von Fritsch (1901–1960), a secretary at the civil service office where he worked. They had two children together.[281] Upon the close of World War II, Hayek restarted a relationship with an old girlfriend, who had married since they first met, but kept it secret until 1948. Hayek and Fritsch divorced in July 1950 and he married his cousin[282] Helene Bitterlich (1900–1996)[283] just a few weeks later, after moving to Arkansas to take advantage of permissive divorce laws.[284] His wife and children were offered settlement and compensation for accepting a divorce. The divorce caused some scandal at LSE, where certain academics refused to have anything to do with Hayek.[284] In a 1978 interview to explain his actions, Hayek stated that he was unhappy in his first marriage and as his wife would not grant him a divorce he had taken steps to obtain one unilaterally.[285]

For a time after his divorce, Hayek rarely visited his children, but kept up more regular contact with them in his older years after moving to Europe.[282][286] Hayek's son, Laurence Hayek (1934–2004) was a distinguished microbiologist.[287] His daughter Christine was an entomologist at the British Museum of Natural History,[2] and she cared for him during his last years, when he had declining health.[286][288]

Hayek had a lifelong interest in biology and was also concerned with ecology and environmental protection. After being awarded his Nobel Prize, he offered his name to be used for endorsements by World Wildlife Fund, National Audubon Society, and the National Trust, a British conservationist organisation. Evolutionary biology was simply one of his interests in natural sciences. Hayek also had an interest in epistemology, which he often applied to his own thinking, as a social scientist. He held that methodological differences in the social sciences and in natural sciences were key to understanding why incompetent policies are often allowed.[289][290]

Hayek was brought up in a non-religious setting and decided from age 15 that he was an agnostic.[49]

He died in 1992 in Freiburg, Germany, where he had lived since leaving Chicago in 1961. Despite his advanced age by the 1980s, he continued to write, even purportedly finishing a book, The Fatal Conceit, in 1988, although its actual authorship is unclear.[15][291]

Legacy and honours

[edit]
Дорожный знак имени Хайека во Фрайбурге-им-Брайсгау, Германия.

Hayek's intellectual presence has remained evident in the years following his death, especially in the universities where he had taught, namely the London School of Economics, the University of Chicago and the University of Freiburg. His influence and contributions have been noted by many. A number of tributes have resulted, many established posthumously:

Известные работы

[ редактировать ]

Родословная

[ редактировать ]

Мать была из семьи фон Юрашек.

См. также

[ редактировать ]
  1. ^ «№34541» . Лондонская газета . 12 августа 1938 г. с. 5182.
  2. ^ Jump up to: а б «Кристина Мария Фелиситас фон Хайек, энтомолог» . Викивиды . Проверено 27 декабря 2023 г.
  3. ^ «Лоуренс Хайек: микробиолог, который в дальнейшей жизни почтил память о работе своего отца» . «Таймс» : 31. 6 августа 2004 г.
  4. ^ Эбенштейн, Алан О. (2003). Путешествие Хайека: разум Фридриха Хайека (Первое изд. Пэлгрейва Макмиллана). Нью-Йорк: Пэлгрейв Макмиллан. ISBN  978-1403960382 .
  5. ^ Колдуэлл, Брюс (2004). Вызов Хайека: интеллектуальная биография Ф.А. Хайека . Чикаго: Издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  0-226-09193-7 .
  6. ^ Шмидц, Дэвид; Беттке, Питер (лето 2021 г.). «Фридрих Хайек» . Стэнфордская энциклопедия философии .
  7. ^ Гэмбл, Эндрю (1996). Хайек: Железная клетка свободы . Рутледж. п. 1. ISBN  978-0-367-00974-8 .
  8. ^ Jump up to: а б Банк Швеции (1974). «Премия Риксбанка Швеции в области экономических наук памяти Альфреда Нобеля 1974 года» .
  9. ^ Скарбек, Дэвид (март 2009 г.). «Влияние Ф.А. Хайека на лауреатов Нобелевской премии» (PDF) . Обзор австрийской экономики . 22 (1): 109–112. CiteSeerX   10.1.1.207.1605 . дои : 10.1007/s11138-008-0069-x . S2CID   144970753 . Архивировано из оригинала (PDF) 27 июля 2011 года.
  10. ^ «Фридрих Август фон Хайек – Факты» . nobelprize.org . Проверено 30 июня 2017 г.
  11. ^ Ротбард, Мюррей Н. (28 января 2010 г.). «Хайек и Нобелевская премия» . Институт Мизеса . Проверено 30 июня 2017 г.
  12. ^ Jump up to: а б «Фридрих А. Хайек» . Институт Мизеса . 20 июня 2014 года . Проверено 3 сентября 2019 г.
  13. ^ «Кейнс против Хайека: гиганты экономики» . Би-би-си . 3 августа 2011 года . Проверено 4 сентября 2019 г.
  14. ^ «Премия Риксбанка Швеции в области экономических наук памяти Альфреда Нобеля 1974 года» . NobelPrize.org . Проверено 4 сентября 2019 г.
  15. ^ Jump up to: а б с д и Питер Г. Кляйн (18 августа 2014 г.). «Биография Ф.А. Хайека (1899–1992)» . Институт Мизеса .
  16. ^ «Аарон Директор, основатель сферы права и экономики» . www-news.uchicago.edu . Архивировано из оригинала 11 марта 2022 года . Проверено 3 сентября 2019 г.
  17. ^ Jump up to: а б с «Командные высоты: Чикагская школа | на канале PBS» . www.pbs.org . Проверено 3 сентября 2019 г.
  18. ^ Бурчак, Теодор А. (12 октября 2006 г.). Социализм после Хайека . Издательство Мичиганского университета. ISBN  978-0472069514 .
  19. ^ «Консерваторам нужно перечитать своего Хайека» . Американский институт предпринимательства – AEI . Проверено 23 февраля 2023 г.
  20. ^ ван дер Воссен, Бас (2022), «Либертарианство» , Стэнфордская энциклопедия философии (изд. Зима 2022 г.) , получено 23 февраля 2023 г.
  21. ^ КЛИТЕР, ПОЛ Б. (1990). «Почему Хайек консерватор» . ARSP: Архивы юридической и социальной философии / Архивы философии права и социальной философии . 76 (4): 467–478. ISSN   0001-2343 . JSTOR   23681094 .
  22. ^ Колдуэлл, Брюс (1 сентября 2020 г.). «Дорога к крепостному праву через 75 лет» . Журнал экономической литературы . 58 (3): 720–748. дои : 10.1257/jel.20191542 . ISSN   0022-0515 . S2CID   201350365 .
  23. ^ Хайек, Фридрих А. (2011). «Почему я не консерватор». Конституция свободы (Окончательное издание). Издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  978-0-226-31539-3 .
  24. ^ Шрепель, Тибо (январь 2015 г.). «Вклад Фридриха Хайека в антимонопольное право и его современное применение». Глобальный антимонопольный обзор ICC : 199–216. ССНН   2548420 .
  25. ^ Ормерод, Пол (2006). «Угасание Фридмана» . www.prospectmagazine.co.uk . Проверено 31 августа 2019 г.
  26. ^ Jump up to: а б Кэтлин, Джордж (1944). «Дорога к крепостному праву» . Природа . 154 (3911): 473–474. Бибкод : 1944Natur.154..473C . дои : 10.1038/154473a0 . S2CID   4071358 .
  27. ^ Jump up to: а б «№49768» . Лондонская газета (Приложение). 16 июня 1984 г. с. 4.
  28. ^ Jump up to: а б с д Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 305.
  29. ^ «Фонд Ханнса Мартина Шлейера / Награды Фонда» . Архивировано из оригинала 25 февраля 2014 года . Проверено 30 апреля 2013 г.
  30. ^ Джордж Буш-старший (18 ноября 1991 г.). «Заявление о вручении Президентской медали Свободы» .
  31. ^ Jump up to: а б Эрроу, Кеннет Дж.; Бернхейм, Б. Дуглас; Фельдштейн, Мартин С.; Макфадден, Дэниел Л.; Потерба, Джеймс М.; Солоу, Роберт М. (2011). «100 лет American Economic Review: 20 лучших статей» . Американский экономический обзор . 101 (1): 1–8. дои : 10.1257/aer.101.1.1 . hdl : 1721.1/114169 .
  32. ^ Алан Эбенштейн (2003). Фридрих Хайек: Биография . п. 12.
  33. ^ Колдуэлл Брюс; Клаузингер, Хансйорг (2021). «Генеалогия Ф.А. Хайека» (PDF) . Университет Дьюка, Центр истории политической экономии (CHOPE) . Рабочий документ CHOPE (2021–2006 гг.). Дарем, Северная Каролина. дои : 10.2139/ssrn.3844091 .
  34. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 12, 312.
  35. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , стр. 62, 248, 284 .
  36. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 7.
  37. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , стр. 7–8.
  38. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 20.
  39. Примечание: Фон Юрашек был статистиком, а позже работал на австрийском правительстве.
  40. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 8.
  41. ^ Джаник, Аллан. Семейные отношения и семейные сходства: Хайек и Витгенштейн .
  42. ^ Эрбахер, Кристиан. Черновик биографии Людвига Витгенштейна, написанный Фридрихом Августом фон Хайеком .
  43. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 245.
  44. ^ Хайек о Хайеке: автобиографический диалог , Фридрих Август Хайек, Routledge, 1994, стр. 51
  45. ^ Молодой Людвиг: жизнь Витгенштейна , 1889–1921, Брайан МакГиннесс, Oxford University Press, 2005, стр. xii
  46. ^ Хайек о Хайеке: автобиографический диалог, Фридрих Август Хайек, Routledge, 1995, стр. 53.
  47. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 9.
  48. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 14.
  49. ^ Jump up to: а б с Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 13.
  50. ^ Jump up to: а б «Устная история Калифорнийского университета в Лос-Анджелесе, 1978 г., интервью с Фридрихом Хайеком, стр. 32–38» . 10 марта 2001 года . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  51. ^ Кресдж, Стивен; Венар, Лейф (2005). Хайек о Хайеке: автобиографический диалог . Рутледж. п. 39. ИСБН  978-0226320625 .
  52. ^ Фридрих Август фон Хайек , ссылка
  53. ^ Дэвид Гордон (8 мая 2009 г.). «Фридрих Хайек как учитель» .
  54. ^ Дейдра Н. Макклоски (2000). Как быть человеком: хотя бы экономистом . Университет Мичигана Пресс. п. 33. ISBN  978-0472067442 .
  55. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 28.
  56. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 22.
  57. ^ Jump up to: а б Некоторые размышления о «Сенсорном порядке» Хайека , Колдуэлл, 2004 г.
  58. ^ Jump up to: а б Сенсорный приказ (1952) об обучении
    • Бакхаус, Юрген Г. (2005). Предпринимательство, деньги и координация: теория культурной эволюции Хайека . Издательство Эдварда Элгара. п. 48. ИСБН  978-1845427955 .
    • Ричард Арена; Аньес Фестре; Натали Лазарик, ред. (2012). Справочник знаний и экономики . Издательство Эдварда Элгара. п. 133. ИСБН  978-1781001028 .
  59. ^ канопиадмин (30 июля 2014 г.). «Венские связи: Альфред Шюц и австрийская школа» . Институт Мизеса . Проверено 2 января 2019 г.
  60. ^ Jump up to: а б Френч, Дуглас (2013), Лисон, Роберт (редактор), «Хайек и Мизес» , Хайек: Совместная биография: влияние части 1, от Мизеса до Бартли , серия «Архивный взгляд на эволюцию экономики», Лондон: Palgrave Macmillan UK , стр. 80–92, doi : 10.1057/9781137328564_6 , ISBN.  978-1137328564 , получено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  61. ^ Эй Джей Теббл, Ф. А. Хайек , Международная издательская группа Continuum, 2010, стр. 4–5.
  62. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 33.
  63. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 35.
  64. ^ Jump up to: а б Лисон, Роберт (2018). Хайек: Совместная биография .
  65. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 23.
  66. ^ Федеричи, Майкл. Эрик Фогелин: Восстановление порядка , ISI Books, 2002, стр. 1
  67. ^ Jump up to: а б «WIFO – О WIFO» . 23 января 2013 года. Архивировано из оригинала 23 января 2013 года . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  68. ^ Баксендейл, Тоби (25 октября 2010 г.). «Битва писем: Кейнс против Хайека 1932, Скидельский против Бесли 2010» . Центр Кобдена . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  69. ^ «Информация» (PDF) . thinkmarkets.files.wordpress.com . 2010.
  70. ^ Малкольм Перрин Макнейр, Ричард Стоктон Мериам, Проблемы экономики бизнеса , McGraw-Hill, 1941, с. 504
  71. ^ Хайек (1945). Ридерс Дайджест Дорога к крепостному праву . Ридерз Дайджест.
  72. Кейнс против Хайека: два экономических гиганта встречаются лицом к лицу Бизнес – BBC News , 2 августа 2011 г.
  73. ^ Гэлбрейт, Дж. К. (1991). «Вспомнился Николас Калдор». Николас Калдор и господствующая экономика: конфронтация или конвергенция? . Нью-Йорк: Пресса Святого Мартина. ISBN  978-0312053567 .
  74. ^ «Автобиография сэра Артура Льюиса» . Нобелевская премия.org . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  75. ^ «Интервью с Дэвидом Рокфеллером» . Архивировано из оригинала 6 июля 2009 года.
  76. ^ «№34541» . Лондонская газета . 12 августа 1938 г. с. 5182.
  77. ^ Jump up to: а б Бриттан, Сэмюэл (2004). «Хайек, Фридрих Август (1899–1992)». Оксфордский национальный биографический словарь (онлайн-изд.). Издательство Оксфордского университета. doi : 10.1093/ref:odnb/51095 . (Требуется подписка или членство в публичной библиотеке Великобритании .)
  78. ^ «Выборы стипендиатов, 1947 г.». Эконометрика . 16 (1): 117–122. Январь 1948 года. JSTOR   1914293 .
  79. ^ канопиадмин (18 августа 2014 г.). «Дорога к крепостному праву» . Институт Мизеса . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  80. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 116.
  81. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 128.
  82. ^ А. Дж. Теббл, Ф. А. Хайек , Международная издательская группа Continuum, 2010, стр. 2010. 8
  83. ^ Бим, Кристофер (3 января 2011 г.). «Проблема со свободой» . Журнал Нью-Йорк . Нью-Йорк Медиа, ООО . Проверено 7 ноября 2015 г.
  84. ^ Jump up to: а б Митч, Дэвид (2015), Лисон, Роберт (редактор), «Мораль против денег: переезд Хайека в Чикагский университет» , Хайек: совместная биография: Часть IV, Англия, порядковая революция и путь к крепостному праву, 1931 г. –50 , Архивный взгляд на эволюцию экономики, Лондон: Palgrave Macmillan UK, стр. 215–255, doi : 10.1057/9781137452603_7 , ISBN  978-1137452603 , получено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  85. ^ Комптон, Джон (2020). Конец эмпатии . Издательство Оксфордского университета.
  86. ^ Милтон и Роуз Фридман, Два счастливчика: Мемуары (Чикаго: U. of Chicago Press, 1998)
  87. ^ Росс Б. Эммет (2010). Элгар Компаньон Чикагской школы экономики . Издательство Эдварда Элгара. стр. 164, 200, 266–267. ISBN  978-1849806664 .
  88. ^ Фридман, Милтон (1951). «Неолиберализм и его перспективы». Фарманд : 89–93.
  89. ^ Йохан Ван Овертвельдт, Чикагская школа: Как Чикагский университет собрал мыслителей, совершивших революцию в экономике и бизнесе (2006), стр. 7, 341–46.
  90. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 270.
  91. ^ Ван Хорн, Роберт (2015), Лисон, Роберт (редактор), «Хайек и Чикагская школа» , Хайек: Совместная биография: Часть V Великое общество свободных людей Хайека , Архивный взгляд на эволюцию экономики , Лондон: Пэлгрейв Macmillan UK, стр. 91–111, номер документа : 10.1057/9781137478245_3 , ISBN.  978-1137478245 , получено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  92. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 267.
  93. ^ «Фонд Джона Саймона Гуггенхайма | Фридрих Август фон Хайек» . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  94. Биография . Архивировано 17 июля 2012 года в Wayback Machine на LibertyStory.net.
  95. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 253.
  96. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 195.
  97. ^ Jump up to: а б Ф.А. Хайек, Конституция свободы (Лондон: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1960)
  98. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 203.
  99. ^ Ф.А. Хайек, по случаю столетия со дня его рождения , Рональд Хамови, Институт Катона
  100. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 209.
  101. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 218.
  102. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 209-210.
  103. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 218.
  104. ^ Jump up to: а б Колдуэлл, Брюс; Монтес, Леонидас (26 сентября 2014 г.). «Фридрих Хайек и его визиты в Чили» (PDF) . Обзор австрийской экономики . 28 (3): 261–309. дои : 10.1007/s11138-014-0290-8 . S2CID   189953475 .
  105. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 254.
  106. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 251-253.
  107. ^ Jump up to: а б с «Премия по экономике 1974 года» . Нобелевская премия.org. 9 октября 1974 года . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  108. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн, с. 263.
  109. ^ Лисон, Роберт (1975). Информационный бюллетень о золоте и серебре . Спрингер. ISBN  978-3319952192 .
  110. ^ Клаузингер, Х. (2010). «Заметка Хайека о практическом исследовании делового цикла». В Х. Хагеманне; Т. Нисидзава; Ю. Икеда (ред.). Австрийская экономика в переходный период: от Карла Менгера до Фридриха Хайека .
  111. ^ Клаузингер, Х. (2012), «Редакционные примечания», Собрание сочинений Ф.А. Хайека , Ф.А. Хайек, Клаузингер, Х. (ред.), vol. VII: Деловые циклы
  112. ^ «Перевод цитаты из блога: «Хайек и крах фондового рынка 1929 года: вот вам и его предсказательные способности» » . 18 декабря 2011 г.
  113. ^ Хайек, Фридрих Август (26 октября 1929 г.), Ежемесячные отчеты Австрийского института экономических исследований (PDF) , стр. 182
  114. ^ «Дорога от крепостничества: Интервью с Ф.А. Хайеком» . Причина.com . 1 июля 1992 года . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  115. ^ «Фридрих Август фон Хайек – Банкетная речь» . Нобелевская премия.org. 10 декабря 1974 года . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  116. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 261.
  117. ^ Ричард Кокетт, Думая о немыслимом. Аналитические центры и экономическая контрреволюция, 1931–1983 (Фонтана, 1995), стр. 174–76.
  118. ^ Джон Ранела, Люди Тэтчер: инсайдерский отчет о политике, власти и личностях (Фонтана, 1992), с. ix.
  119. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 291-292.
  120. ^ Jump up to: а б с Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 293.
  121. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 294.
  122. ^ «Письма в редакцию: либеральный пакт с лейбористами», The Times (31 марта 1977 г.), стр. 15.
  123. ^ «Письма в редакцию: либеральный пакт с лейбористами», The Times (2 апреля 1977 г.), стр. 15.
  124. ^ «Письма в редакцию: социалистические цели Германии», The Times (13 апреля 1977 г.), стр. 13.
  125. ^ «Письма в редакцию: опасности для личной свободы», The Times (11 июля 1978 г.), стр. 15.
  126. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 300-301.
  127. ^ Мартин Андерсон, «Революция» (Харкорт Брейс Йованович, 1988), с. 164
  128. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 207-208.
  129. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 301.
  130. ^ Jump up to: а б Насар, Сильвия (19 ноября 1991 г.). «Бизнес-профиль; забытый экономист, удостоенный награды президента» . Нью-Йорк Таймс . ISSN   0362-4331 . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  131. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 317.
  132. ^ "О" . Журнал права и свободы Нью-Йоркского университета . Архивировано из оригинала 17 мая 2014 года . Проверено 15 мая 2014 г.
  133. ^ Мизес, Людвиг (1912). Теория денег и кредита .
  134. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1931). Цены и производство .
  135. ^ Австрийская теория деловых циклов: старые уроки для современной экономической политики? , Опперс, Международный валютный фонд
  136. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих (2012). Хорошие деньги: Часть 2 . Издательство Чикагского университета. п. 202. ИСБН  978-0226321196 .
  137. См. главу «Сотрудничество с Кейнсом и полемика с Хайеком» , Хайнц Д. Курц и Нери Сальвадори, «Вклад Пьеро Сраффы в экономику», в «Критических эссе о наследии Пьеро Сраффы в экономике» , под ред. HD Kurz, (Кембридж: Издательство Кембриджского университета, 2000), стр. 3–24. ISBN   978-0521580892
  138. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1989). Собрание сочинений Ф.А. Хайека . Издательство Чикагского университета. п. 202. ИСБН  978-0226320977 .
  139. ^ Jump up to: а б Уайт, Лоуренс Х. (2008). «Усугубили ли Хайек и Роббинс Великую депрессию?» . Журнал денег, кредита и банковского дела . 40 (4). Уайли-Блэквелл : 751–768. дои : 10.1111/j.1538-4616.2008.00134.x . JSTOR   25096276 .
  140. ^ Jump up to: а б с Николас Калдор (1942). «Профессор Хайек и эффект концертины». Экономика . 9 (36): 359–382. дои : 10.2307/2550326 . JSTOR   2550326 .
  141. ^ Ф.А. Хайек, «Размышления о чистой теории денег г-на Дж. М. Кейнса», Economica , 11 , S. 270–95 (1931).
  142. ^ Ф.А. Хайек, Цены и производство. Архивировано 12 августа 2014 г. в Wayback Machine (Лондон: Routledge, 1931).
  143. ^ П. Сраффа, «Доктор Хайек о деньгах и капитале», Economic Journal , 42 , S. 42–53 (1932).
  144. ^ Брюс Колдуэлл, Вызов Хайека: интеллектуальная биография Ф.А. Хайека (Чикаго: University of Chicago Press, 2004), стр. 179. ISBN   0226091937
  145. ^ Николас Калдор (1939). «Капиталоемкость и торговый цикл». Экономика . 6 (21): 40–66. дои : 10.2307/2549077 . JSTOR   2549077 .
  146. ^ Jump up to: а б Р.В. Гаррисон , «Ф.А. Хайек как «мистер флуктуации»: в защиту «технической экономики» Хайека» , Журнал Общества Хайека (LSE), 5 (2), 1 (2003).
  147. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1941). Чистая теория капитала .
  148. ^ Хайек и Фридман: лицом к лицу , Гаррисон, Обернский университет
  149. ^ Мизес, Людвиг. Экономический расчет в Социалистическом Содружестве .
  150. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих (1935). Коллективистское экономическое планирование . Г. Рутледж. ISBN  978-1610161626 .
  151. ^ Ланге, О. 1967. Компьютер и рынок при социализме.
  152. ^ Ланге, 1938, Об экономической теории социализма, University of Minnesota Press.
  153. ^ Милтон Фридман, «Ланге о гибкости цен и занятости», Очерки позитивной экономики .
  154. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1937). Экономика и знания .
  155. ^ Хайн Шредер, «Коуз, Хайек и иерархия», В: С. Линденберг и Хайн Шредер, реж., Междисциплинарные перспективы организационных исследований, Pergamon Press
  156. ^ Дума, Сице и Хайн Шредер , 2013. «Экономические подходы к организациям». 5-е издание. Лондон: Пирсон, ISBN   978-0273735298
  157. ^ Чистая теория капитала ( pdf ), Чикаго: University of Chicago Press, 1941/2007 (Том 12 собрания сочинений): стр. 90.
  158. ^ Jump up to: а б Колдуэлл, Брюс. «Хайек, Фридрих Август фон (1899–1992)». Новый экономический словарь Пэлгрейва. Третье издание. Ред. Стивен Н. Дюрлауф и Лоуренс Э. Блюм. Пэлгрейв Макмиллан, 2018.
  159. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1952). Контрреволюция науки .
  160. ^ Репке, Вильгельм . Моральные основы гражданского общества . Издатели транзакций. ISBN  978-1412837859 – через Google Книги.
  161. ^ Джеральд Эдельман , Нейронный дарвинизм, 1987, с. 25
  162. ^ Хоакин Фустер, Память в коре головного мозга: эмпирический подход к нейронным сетям у человека и нечеловеческих приматов. Кембридж: MIT Press, 1995, стр. 87–88.
  163. ^ Хоакин Фустер, «Сетевая память», Тенденции в нейронауках, 1997. Том. 20, № 10. (октябрь): 451–459.
  164. ^ ван де Хаар, Эдвин. « Людвиг фон Мизес и Фридрих Хайек: Федерация как последняя надежда» ( PDF) . Космос + Такси: исследования в области возникающего порядка . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  165. ^ Хайек, Фридрих. Дорога к крепостному праву . Собрание сочинений Ф.А. Хайека. Издательство Чикагского университета . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  166. ^ Розенбойм, Ор (2014). « Барбара Вуттон, Фридрих Хайек и дебаты о демократическом федерализме в 1940-х годах » . Обзор международной истории . 36 (5): 894–918. дои : 10.1080/07075332.2013.871320 . JSTOR   24703266 . S2CID   154887466 . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  167. ^ ван де Хаар, Эдвин. « Спонтанный порядок Хайека и международный баланс сил» ( PDF) . Независимый обзор . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  168. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (17 апреля 2017 г.). «Экономические условия межгосударственного федерализма» . Фонд экономического образования (первоначально опубликовано в New Commonwealth Quarterly, V, № 2 (сентябрь 1939 г.), 131–49) . Архивировано из оригинала 15 октября 2022 года . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  169. ^ Ньентидт, Дэниел. « Ф.А. Хайек и мир завтрашнего дня: принципы международного федерализма» ( PDF) . Космос + Такси: исследования в области возникающего порядка . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  170. ^ Мазини, Фабио. « Федерализм Хайека и становление европейской интеграции» ( PDF) . Космос + Такси: исследования в области возникающего порядка . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  171. ^ Кристенсен, Брэндон. « Возрождение либертарианской межгосударственной федералистской традиции: американское предложение» ( PDF) . Независимый обзор . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  172. ^ Шпикер, Йорг (2014). « Ф.А. Хайек и возрождение либерального интернационализма » . Обзор международной истории . 36 (5): 919–942. дои : 10.1080/07075332.2014.900814 . S2CID   143713445 . Проверено 14 октября 2022 г.
  173. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих Август (1980). Индивидуализм и экономический порядок (Переиздание). Чикаго Лондон: издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  0-226-32093-6 .
  174. ^ Хайек, Фридрих А. фон (2011). Конституция свободы: окончательное издание . Чикаго, Иллинойс: Univ. из Чикаго Пресс. ISBN  978-0-226-31539-3 .
  175. ^ Хайек, Фридрих А. фон (2012). Закон, законодательство и свобода: новое утверждение либеральных принципов справедливости и политической экономии . Лондон (ua): Routledge. ISBN  978-0-415-52229-8 .
  176. ^ Фергюсон, Адам (1767). Очерк истории гражданского общества . Проект Гутенберг : Т. Каделл, Лондон. п. 205.
  177. ^ Эбелинг, Ричард М. (6 января 2018 г.). «Цена — единственный язык, на котором все говорят | Ричард М. Эбелинг» . www.fee.org . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  178. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих (1988). Роковое самомнение .
  179. ^ де Бенуа, Ален (1998). «Хайек: Критика». Телос . 1998 (110): 71–104. дои : 10.3817/1298110071 . S2CID   219203705 .
  180. ^ Лами, Энди (24 сентября 2014 г.). «Экосистемы как спонтанные порядки». ССНР   2501745 .
  181. ^ Лами, Энди (24 сентября 2014 г.). «Экосистемы как спонтанные порядки». стр. 2–11. ССНР   2501745 .
  182. ^ Лами, Энди (24 сентября 2014 г.). «Экосистемы как спонтанные порядки». стр. 12–13. ССНР   2501745 .
  183. ^ «Основное Хайека» (PDF) . Институт Фрейзера . Архивировано из оригинала (PDF) 28 апреля 2021 года . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  184. ^ Чанг, Ха-Джун (2014). «4». Экономика: Руководство пользователя . Лондон: Penguin Books Limited. ISBN  978-0718197032 .
  185. ^ Хайек, Ф.А. Дорога к крепостному праву , гл. 9
  186. ^ Стрингем, Эдвард; Живицкий, Тодд (20 января 2011 г.). «Хайекский анархизм». ССНН   1744364 .
  187. ^ «Хайек о социальном страховании» . Вашингтон Пост .
  188. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1976). Денационализация денег .
  189. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (2011) [1960]. Хамови, Рональд (ред.). Конституция свободы (Окончательное издание). Чикаго: Издательство Чикагского университета. п. 405. ИСБН  978-0-226-31539-3 .
  190. ^ Уопшот, Николас (2011), Кейнс Хайек: Столкновение, которое определило современную экономику , Нью-Йорк: WW Norton & Company, стр. 291
  191. ^ Харкорт, Бернар (12 сентября 2012 г.). «Как Пол Райан порабощает книгу Фридриха Хайека «Дорога к рабству» . Хранитель . Проверено 27 декабря 2014 г.
  192. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (2007) [1944]. Колдуэлл, Брюс (ред.). Дорога к крепостному праву (Окончательное издание). Чикаго: Издательство Чикагского университета. стр. 147–148 . ISBN  978-0226320557 .
  193. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1976). Закон, законодательство и свобода . Том. 2. Чикаго: Издательство Чикагского университета. п. 87. ИСБН  978-0226320830 .
  194. ^ Теббл, Адам Джеймс (2009). «Хайек и социальная справедливость: критика». Критический обзор международной социальной и политической философии . 12 (4): 581–604. дои : 10.1080/13698230903471343 . S2CID   145380847 .
  195. ^ Мираж социальной справедливости , гл. 10
  196. ^ Jump up to: а б Мираж социальной справедливости , гл. 12
  197. ^ Конституция свободы , гл. 6
  198. ^ Даймонд, Артур М. (осень 1980 г.). «Ф.А. Хайек о конструктивизме и этике». Журнал либертарианских исследований . IV/4 : 353–365.
  199. ^ Кукатас, Чандран (1990). Хайек и современный либерализм . Издательство Оксфордского университета. п. 215.
  200. ^ Н. П. Барри (1994), «Дорога к свободе - социальная и экономическая философия Хайека», в книге Бирнер Дж. и ван Зийп Р. (ред.) Хайек, Координация и эволюция - Его наследие в философии, политике, Экономика и история идей, стр. 141–163. Лондон: Рутледж.
  201. ^ Милтон Фридман и Анна Дж. Шварц, «Имеет ли правительство какую-либо роль в деньгах?» (1986)
  202. Джон Грей, «Фридрих Хайек, которого я знал, и что он делал правильно и неправильно» (30 июля 2015 г.)
  203. ^ Брюс Колдуэлл, Вызов Хайека: интеллектуальная биография Ф.А. Хайека (Чикаго: University of Chicago Press, 2004), стр. 347–348
  204. ^ Jump up to: а б Фаррант, Эндрю; Макфейл, Эдвард; Бергер, Себастьян (2012). «Предотвращение «злоупотреблений» демократией: Хайек, «военный узурпатор» и переходная диктатура в Чили?». Американский журнал экономики и социологии . 71 (3): 513–538. дои : 10.1111/j.1536-7150.2012.00824.x .
  205. ^ Грег Грандин, профессор истории Нью-Йоркского университета, Мастерская Империи: Латинская Америка, Соединенные Штаты и рост нового империализма , стр. 172–173, Metropolitan, 2006, ISBN   0805077383 .
  206. ^ Дэн Авнон, Либерализм и его практика , стр. 56, Рутледж, 1999 г., ISBN   0415193540 .
  207. ^ «Предотвращение «злоупотреблений» демократией: Хайек, «военный узурпатор» и переходная диктатура в Чили?» (PDF) . Американский журнал экономики и социологии .
  208. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1979) Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том 3: Политический порядок свободных людей. Рутледж 1982. с. 195
  209. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1979) Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том 3: Политический порядок свободных людей. Рутледж 1982. с. 56
  210. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих (1976) Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том 2: Мираж социальной справедливости . Рутледж, 1982. стр. 58)
  211. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 390.
  212. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 295.
  213. ^ Лисон, Роберт (2015) Хайек: Совместная биография: Часть II, Австрия, Америка и восхождение Гитлера, 1899–1933. Пэлгрейв Макмиллан, 2015. с. 112
  214. ^ Jump up to: а б Лисон, Роберт (2018) Хайек: Совместная биография: Часть XV: Чикагская школа экономики, «Удача» Хайека и Нобелевская премия по экономике 1974 года. Пэлгрейв Макмиллан, 2015. с. 175
  215. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 299.
  216. ^ Лисон, Роберт (2015) Хайек: Совместная биография: Часть II, Австрия, Америка и восхождение Гитлера, 1899–1933. Пэлгрейв Макмиллан, 2015. с. 85
  217. ^ Слободян, Куинн (2018) Глобалисты: конец империи и рождение неолиберализма . Издательство Гарвардского университета: Кембридж, Массачусетс, с. 154
  218. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы. Рутледж, 2006. с. 76
  219. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 109
  220. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 111
  221. ^ Jump up to: а б Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 110
  222. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 113
  223. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы. Рутледж, 2006. с. 112
  224. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 80
  225. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 270
  226. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 269
  227. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (1960) Конституция свободы . Рутледж, 2006. с. 273
  228. ^ Теббл, Адам Джеймс (1 декабря 2009 г.). «Хайек и социальная справедливость: критика» . Критический обзор международной социальной и политической философии . 12 (4): 581–604. дои : 10.1080/13698230903471343 . ISSN   1369-8230 . S2CID   145380847 .
  229. ^ Фукуяма, Фрэнсис (6 мая 2011 г.). «Фридрих А. Хайек, скептик большого правительства» . Нью-Йорк Таймс . ISSN   0362-4331 . Проверено 25 февраля 2023 г.
  230. ^ Беттке, Питер Дж. (1995). «Возвращение Хайека к пути к крепостному праву: провал правительства в аргументации против социализма» . Восточный экономический журнал . 21 (1): 7–26. ISSN   0094-5056 . JSTOR   40325611 .
  231. ^ Скарбек, Дэвид (2009). «Влияние Ф.А. Хайека на лауреатов Нобелевской премии» . Обзор австрийской экономики . 22 (1): 109–112. дои : 10.1007/s11138-008-0069-x . S2CID   144970753 .
  232. ^ Смит Саймон
    • Саймон, Герберт (1981). Науки об искусственном (2-е изд.). Кембридж: MIT Press. Никто не охарактеризовал рыночные механизмы лучше, чем Фридрих фон Хайек. : 41 
  233. ^ Самуэльсон, Пол А. (2009). «Несколько воспоминаний о Фридрихе фон Хайеке (1899–1992)» . Журнал экономического поведения и организации . 69 : 1–4. дои : 10.1016/j.jebo.2008.07.001 .
  234. ^ Сборник научных статей Пола А. Самуэльсона, том 5, с. 315.
  235. ^ Фриц Махлуп, Очерки Хайека , Routledge, 2003. с. 14.
  236. ^ Сильвия Насар, «Большая погоня: история экономического гения» , Саймон и Шустер, 2011, стр. 402
  237. ^ Лоуренс Саммерс, цитата из книги «Командные высоты: битва между правительством и рынком, который переделывает современный мир» Дэниела Ергина и Джозефа Станислава . Нью-Йорк: Саймон и Шустер. 1998, стр. 150–151.
  238. ^ «Уважаемые члены Филадельфийского общества» (PDF) . Архивировано из оригинала (PDF) 18 января 2012 года . Проверено 5 мая 2012 г.
  239. ^ См. Хакоэн, 2000.
  240. ^ См. Веймер и Палермо, 1982 г.
  241. См. Birner, 2001, а информацию о взаимном влиянии, которое они оказали на идеи друг друга об эволюции, Birner 2009.
  242. ^ Милтон и Роуз Фридман, Два счастливчика: Мемуары (U. of Chicago Press), 1998. с. 333
  243. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 266.
  244. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 271.
  245. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 272.
  246. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 81.
  247. ^ например, Волин 2004 г.
  248. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 275.
  249. ^ Берлинер, MS (ред.), Письма Айн Рэнд . Нью-Йорк, Даттон, 1995. стр. 299.
  250. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 274.
  251. ^ «Модель Википедии следует за Хайеком» . Уолл Стрит Джорнал . 15 апреля 2009 г.
  252. ^ Фанеф, Эмиль. «Хайек и Биткойн | AIER» . www.aier.org . Проверено 28 марта 2024 г.
  253. ^ Поллок, Алекс Дж. (30 марта 2022 г.). «Являются ли криптовалюты великим спасением Хайека? – Алекс Дж. Поллок» . Закон и свобода . Проверено 28 марта 2024 г.
  254. ^ Кеннет Р. Гувер, Экономика как идеология: Кейнс, Ласки, Хайек и создание современной политики (2003), с. 213
  255. ^ Седербаум, Якоб Э:сон (2020). Современный консерватизм: философия, основные идеи и ориентации в преемственности Берка . Борос: Речито. стр. 38, 116–117, 269. ISBN.  978-91-7765-497-1 .
  256. ^ Фосетт, Эдмунд (2018). Либерализм: жизнь идеи (2-е изд.). Издательство Принстонского университета. п. 327. ИСБН  9780691180380 .
  257. ^ Хэзлетт, Томас В. (1 сентября 1979 г.). «Ф.А. Хайек: классический либерал | Томас В. Хэзлетт» . www.fee.org . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  258. ^ Богус, Карл (2011). Бакли . Издательство Блумсбери США. ISBN  978-1608193554 .
  259. ^ ЭХХ Грин, Идеологии консерватизма. Консервативные политические идеи в двадцатом веке (Оксфорд: Oxford University Press, 2004), с. 259.
  260. ^ Jump up to: а б Сэмюэл Бриттан, «Многоликость либерализма», ft.com , 22 января 2010 г.
  261. ^ «Ф.А. Хайек | МПС» . Архивировано из оригинала 14 февраля 2016 года . Проверено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  262. ^ Хербер, Томас (2019), Хербер, Томас; Анкетиль, Ален (ред.), «Корни неолиберализма у Фридриха фон Хайека» , «Экономическая теория и глобализация » , Cham: Springer International Publishing, стр. 169–194, doi : 10.1007/978-3-030-23824-7_8 , ISBN  978-3030238247 , S2CID   202307278 , получено 28 апреля 2021 г.
  263. ^ Беттке, Питер Дж. (2002). Почему перестройка провалилась: политика и экономика социалистической трансформации . Рутледж . ISBN  978-1134886319 . Проверено 2 января 2019 г.
  264. ^ Маккиннон, Рональд (1992). «Спонтанный порядок на пути назад от социализма: азиатская перспектива». Американский экономический обзор . 82 (2). Американская экономическая ассоциация : 31–36. JSTOR   2117371 .
  265. ^ Истерли, Уильям (2006). Бремя белого человека: почему усилия Запада по оказанию помощи остальным принесли так много зла и так мало добра . Книги о пингвинах . ISBN  978-1101218129 .
  266. ^ Уайт, Уильям Р. (2009). «Современная макроэкономика находится на неправильном пути» (PDF) . Финансы и развитие . Международный валютный фонд .
  267. ^ Хоффманн, Андреас; Шнабль, Гюнтер (2011). «Порочный круг маний, кризисов и асимметричных политических мер – взгляд на чрезмерные инвестиции». Мировая экономика . 34 (3). Уайли : 382–403. дои : 10.1111/j.1467-9701.2011.01334.x . S2CID   153097003 . ССНН   1513171 .
  268. ^ Шнабль, Гюнтер; Хоффманн, Андреас (2008). «Денежно-кредитная политика, растущая ликвидность и лопнувшие пузыри на новых и развивающихся рынках – взгляд на чрезмерные инвестиции» (PDF) . Мировая экономика . 31 (9). Уайли : 1226–1252 гг. дои : 10.1111/j.1467-9701.2008.01126.x . S2CID   154603748 . ССНР   1018342 .
  269. ^ Качаноски, Николя (2014). «Влияние денежно-кредитной политики США в Колумбии и Панаме (2002–2007 гг.)». Ежеквартальный обзор экономики и финансов . Том. 54, нет. 3. Эльзевир . стр. 428–436. ССНН   2170566 .
  270. ^ Бруннермайер, Маркус К .; Шнабель, Изабель (9 июня 2016 г.). «12. Пузыри и центральные банки: исторические перспективы» . В Бордо, Майкл Д .; Эйтрхейм, Эйвинд; Фландро, Марк; Квигстад, Ян Ф. (ред.). Центральные банки на перепутье: чему мы можем научиться из истории? . Нью-Йорк: Издательство Кембриджского университета . ISBN  978-1107149663 .
  271. ^ Тейлор, Джон Б. (2007). Жилищная и денежно-кредитная политика (PDF) (Отчет). Рабочие документы НБЭР. Том. 13682. Национальное бюро экономических исследований .
  272. ^ «Лоуренс Х. Уайт о денежно-кредитной политике, свободной банковской деятельности и финансовом кризисе | Mercatus» . mercatus.org . 13 декабря 2011 года . Проверено 19 сентября 2016 г.
  273. ^ Самнер, Скотт Б. (2014). «Таргирование номинального ВВП: простое правило для улучшения показателей ФРС» (PDF) . Катонский журнал . Том. 34, нет. 2. Институт Катона . стр. 315–337 . Проверено 24 июля 2019 г.
  274. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (2008). Салерно, Джозеф Т. (ред.). Цены, производство и другие работы о деньгах, деловом цикле и золотом стандарте (PDF) . Оберн, Алабама : Институт Людвига фон Мизеса . п. 297. ИСБН  978-1933550220 . Архивировано из оригинала (PDF) 31 июля 2020 года . Проверено 24 июля 2019 г.
  275. ^ Хайек, Фридрих (9 апреля 1975 г.). «Дискуссия с Фридрихом А. фон Хайеком» (PDF) (интервью). Вашингтон, округ Колумбия: Американский институт предпринимательства . стр. 12–13. ISBN  0844731900 .
  276. ^ Хоффманн, Андреас; Шнабль, Гюнтер (2016). «Неблагоприятные последствия нетрадиционной денежно-кредитной политики» (PDF) . Катонский журнал . 36 (3). Институт Катона .
  277. ^ «Расшифровка: Фридрих Хайек» . pbs.org . Проверено 14 февраля 2015 г.
  278. ^ Анджи Валицкий, «Либерализм в Польше», Critical Review, Зима, 1988, стр. 9.
  279. ^ Дик Арми, «Обращение к посвящению аудитории Хайека», Институт Катона , Вашингтон, округ Колумбия, 9 мая 1995 г.
  280. ^ Вацлав Клаус, «Третьего выхода нет: создание капиталистической Чехословакии», Reason, 1990, (июнь): 28–31.
  281. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 44.
  282. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 169.
  283. ^ Эбенштейн, с. 169.
  284. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн, с. 155.
  285. ^ Армен А. Алчян берет интервью у Фридриха А. Хайека (Часть I) . Интервью Хайека . Событие происходит в 48:50. Архивировано из оригинала 31 августа 2021 года . Проверено 31 августа 2021 г.
  286. ^ Jump up to: а б Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 297.
  287. ^ «Лоуренс Хайек» . Независимый . 7 сентября 2004 г.
  288. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 316.
  289. ^ Бек, Наоми (декабрь 2009 г.). «В поисках правильного научного подхода: взгляды Хайека на биологию, методологию и природу экономики» . Наука в контексте . 22 (4): 567–585. дои : 10.1017/S0269889709990160 . ISSN   1474-0664 . ПМИД   20509429 . S2CID   46364934 .
  290. ^ Эбенштейн 2001 , с. 225.
  291. ^ «Свобода – роковой обман» . 22 июня 2008 г. Архивировано из оригинала 22 июня 2008 г. Проверено 1 июня 2022 г.
  292. ^ «Хайек» . www.lsesu.com .
  293. ^ Эллис, Лидия. «Об Оксфордском обществе Хайека» . Оксфордское общество Хайека. Архивировано из оригинала 4 марта 2016 года . Проверено 6 ноября 2015 г.
  294. ^ «Жилищный кризис: должны ли городские районы расти или разрастаться, чтобы жилье оставалось доступным?» . Институт Катона . 29 ноября 2016 года . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  295. ^ «Фонд Хайека для ученых | Институт гуманитарных исследований» . Theihs.org. Архивировано из оригинала 16 июля 2009 года . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  296. ^ «Экономика | Премия Ф.А. Хайека за эссе» . Экономика . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  297. ^ «Премия Риксбанка Швеции в области экономических наук памяти Альфреда Нобеля 1974 года» . NobelPrize.org . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  298. ^ «Хайекфонд.ком» . Hayekfund.com. Архивировано из оригинала 20 сентября 2011 года . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г.
  299. ^ «Премия Риксбанка Швеции в области экономических наук памяти Альфреда Нобеля 1974 года» . NobelPrize.org . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  300. ^ «Фридрих Август фон Хайек | Орден за заслуги» . www.orden-pourlemerite.de . Проверено 27 апреля 2021 г.
  301. ^ «Почетный кавалер, 1984 г., награжден королевой Елизаветой II» .
  302. ^ «Ответ на парламентский вопрос» (PDF) (на немецком языке). п. 885 . Проверено 24 февраля 2013 г.
  303. ^ «Стипендия Ф.А. Хайека в области политологии и экономики» (PDF) .
  304. ^ Хайек, ФА (1978). Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том . Издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  978-0226320861 . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г. - через Google Книги.
  305. ^ Хайек, ФА (1978). Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том . Издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  978-0226320830 . Проверено 14 сентября 2011 г. - через Google Книги.
  306. ^ Хайек, ФА (1981). Закон, законодательство и свобода, Том 3: Политический порядок свободного народа . Издательство Чикагского университета. ISBN  978-0226320908 .
  307. ^ Алан Эбенштейн: Расследование: Роковой обман. Архивировано 12 февраля 2008 года в Wayback Machine . Свобода 19 :3 (март 2005 г.)
  308. ^ Ян Джарви (редактор), Карл Милфорд (редактор), Дэвид Миллер (редактор) (2006), Карл Поппер : оценка столетия, том. 1: Жизнь, времена и ценности в мире фактов , стр. 120, 295, ISBN   978-0754653752

Библиография

[ редактировать ]
  • Бирнер, Джек (2001). «Проблема разума и тела и социальная эволюция», Рабочий документ CEEL 1-02.
  • Бирнер, Джек и Руди ван Зийп, ред. (1994). Хайек: Координация и эволюция: его наследие в философии, политике, экономике и истории идей. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Бирнер, Джек (2009). «От группового отбора к экологическим нишам. Переосмысление эволюционной теории Поппером в свете теории культуры Хайека», в под ред. С. Парусниковой и Р. С. Коэна. (весна 2009 г.). «Переосмысление Поппера», Бостонские исследования философии науки . Том. 272
  • Беттке, Питер Дж. (1995). «Возвращение Хайека к крепостному праву: провал правительства в аргументации против социализма». Восточный экономический журнал . 21 (1): 7–26. JSTOR   40325611 .
  • Бриттан, Сэмюэл (2004). «Хайек, Фридрих Август (1899–1992)». Оксфордский национальный биографический словарь (онлайн-изд.). Издательство Оксфордского университета. doi : 10.1093/ref:odnb/51095 . (Требуется подписка или членство в публичной библиотеке Великобритании .)
  • Колдуэлл, Брюс (2005). Вызов Хайека: интеллектуальная биография Ф.А. Хайека [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Колдуэлл, Брюс (1997). «Хайек и социализм». Журнал экономической литературы . 35 (4): 1856–1890. JSTOR   2729881 .
  • Коэн, Ави Дж. (2003). «Спор о Хайеке и Найте Капитале: неуместность окольности или процессы очистки во времени?» История политической экономии 35 (3): 469–490. ISSN   0018-2702 Полный текст: онлайн в Project Muse, Swetswise и Ebsco.
  • Клаве, Фрэнсис (2015). «Сравнительное исследование либерализмов (или неолиберализмов) Липпмана и Хайека». Европейский журнал истории экономической мысли . 22 (6): 978–999. дои : 10.1080/09672567.2015.1093522 . S2CID   146137987 .
  • Доэрти, Брайан (2007). Радикалы за капитализм: свободная история современного американского либертарианского движения [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Дума, Сице и Хайн Шредер (2013). «Экономические подходы к организациям». 5-е издание. Лондон: Пирсон, ISBN   978-0273735298
  • Эбелинг, Ричард М. (март 2004 г.). «Ф.А. Хайек и дорога к крепостному праву : признание шестидесятой годовщины» ( The Freeman
  • Эбелинг, Ричард М. (март 2001 г.). «Ф.А. Хайек: Биография» Институт Людвига фон Мизеса
  • Эбелинг, Ричард М. (май 1999 г.). «Фридрих А. Хайек: столетняя признательность» The Freeman
  • Эбенштейн, Алан (2001). Фридрих Хайек: Биография . Бейзингсток: Palgrave Macmillan Trade. ISBN  978-0312233440 .
  • Фельдман, Жан-Филипп (1999). «Критика Хайеком Всеобщей декларации прав человека». Журнал экономистов и гуманитарных исследований . 9 (4): 1145–6396. дои : 10.2202/1145-6396.1172 .
  • Фроуэн, С. изд. (1997). Хайек: экономист и социальный философ
  • Гэмбл, Эндрю (1996). Железная клетка свободы , анализ идей Хайека [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Голдсуорси, доктор медицинских наук (1986). «Политическая и правовая философия Хайека: Введение» [1986] SydLawRw 3; 11(1) Сиднейский юридический обзор 44
  • Грей, Джон (1998). Хайек о свободе [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Хакоэн, Малах (2000). Карл Поппер: годы становления, 1902–1945 гг. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Хамови, Рональд (2008). «Хайек, Фридрих А. (1899–1992)» . Энциклопедия либертарианства . Таузенд-Оукс, Калифорния: Сейдж; Институт Катона. стр. 218–220. дои : 10.4135/9781412965811.n131 . ISBN  978-1412965804 . LCCN   2008009151 . OCLC   750831024 .
  • Хорвиц, Стивен (2005). «Фридрих Хайек, австрийский экономист». Журнал истории экономической мысли 27 (1): 71–85. ISSN   1042-7716 Полный текст: в Swetswise, Ingenta и Ebsco.
  • Иссинг, О. (1999). Хайек, валютная конкуренция и Европейский валютный союз [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Джонс, Дэниел Стедман. (2012) Хозяева Вселенной: Хайек, Фридман и рождение неолиберальной политики (Princeton University Press; 424 страницы)
  • Каспер, Шерил (2002). Возрождение принципа невмешательства в американскую макроэкономическую теорию: пример ее пионеров . Глава. 4
  • Клей, Роланд (1994). Социально-политическая мысль Хайека . Оксфордский университет. Нажимать. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Лисон, Роберт, изд. Хайек: Совместная биография, Часть I: Влияния, от Мизеса до Бартли (Пэлгрейв Макмиллан, 2013), 241 страница [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Мюллер, Джерри З. (2002). Разум и рынок: капитализм в западной мысли . Якорные книги. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Марш, Лесли (ред.) (2011). Хайек в мыслях: Философская психология Хайека . Достижения австрийской экономики. Изумруд [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • О'Ши, Джерри (2020). «Духовная наука Хайека», Современная интеллектуальная история, первый взгляд, стр. 1–26, дои : 10.1017/S1479244320000517
  • Павлик, Ян (2004). nb.vse.cz Архивировано 16 февраля 2012 года в Wayback Machine . Ф.А. фон Хайек и теория спонтанного порядка. Профессиональное издательство 2004, Прага, profespubl.cz
  • Плант, Раймонд (2009). Неолиберальное государственное издательство Оксфордского университета, 312 страниц. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Прессман, Стивен (2006). Пятьдесят крупнейших экономистов (2-е изд.). Лондон: Рутледж.
  • Розеноф, Теодор (1974). «Свобода, планирование и тоталитаризм: восприятие пути Ф.А. Хайека к крепостному праву», Canadian Review of American Studies
  • Самуэльсон, Пол А. (2009). «Несколько воспоминаний о Фридрихе фон Хайеке (1899–1992)», Журнал экономического поведения и организации , 69 (1), стр. 1–4. Перепечатано в J. Bradford DeLong <eblog
  • Самуэльсон, Ричард А. (1999). «Реакция на путь к крепостному праву». Современный век 41 (4): 309–317. ISSN   0026-7457 Полный текст: в Ebsco.
  • Шредер, Хейн (1993). «Коуз, Хайек и иерархия», В: С. Линденберг и Хайн Шредер , ред., Междисциплинарные перспективы организационных исследований, Оксфорд: Pergamon Press. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Ширмур, Джереми (1996). Хайек и после: Хайекианский либерализм как исследовательская программа . Рутледж. [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Теббл, Адам Джеймс (2009). «Хайек и социальная справедливость: критика». Критический обзор международной социальной и политической философии . 12 (4): 581–604. дои : 10.1080/13698230903471343 . S2CID   145380847 .
  • Теббл, Адам Джеймс (2013). Ф.А. Хайек . Академик Блумсбери. ISBN   978-1441109064 . ОСЛК   853506722
  • Таучи, Джон (2005). Хайек и права человека: основы минималистского подхода к праву . Эдвард Элгар [ ISBN отсутствует ]
  • Ванберг, В. (2001). «Хайек, Фридрих А. фон (1899–1992),» Международная энциклопедия социальных и поведенческих наук , стр. 6482–6486. два : 10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/00254-0
  • Вернон, Ричард (1976). «Великое общество» и «Открытое общество»: либерализм у Хайека и Поппера». Канадский журнал политической науки . 9 (2): 261–276. дои : 10.1017/s0008423900043717 . S2CID   146616606 .
  • Уопшот, Николас (2011). Кейнс Хайек: Столкновение, которое определило современную экономику , (WW Norton & Company) 382 страницы ISBN   978-0393077483 ; освещает дебаты с Кейнсом в письмах, статьях, беседах и учениками двух экономистов.
  • Веймер В. и Палермо Д., ред. (1982). Познание и символические процессы . Лоуренс Эрлбаум Ассошиэйтс. Содержит эссе Хайека « Сенсорный порядок через 25 лет» с «Дискуссией».
  • Волин, Ричард . (2004). Соблазнение неразумия: интеллектуальный роман с фашизмом от Ницше до постмодернизма. Издательство Принстонского университета, Принстон. [ ISBN отсутствует ]

Введение

[ редактировать ]

Первоисточники

[ редактировать ]
  • Хайек, Фридрих. Собрание сочинений Ф.А. Хайека, изд. У. В. Бартли, III и другие (University of Chicago Press, 1988–); «План собрания сочинений Ф.А. Хайека» на 19 томов; отрывок из тома 2 и текстовый поиск; том 7 2012 отрывок.
[ редактировать ]
Arc.Ask3.Ru: конец переведенного документа.
Arc.Ask3.Ru
Номер скриншота №: e2a409aeea56ce0eec2da0ad349bf561__1722196260
URL1:https://arc.ask3.ru/arc/aa/e2/61/e2a409aeea56ce0eec2da0ad349bf561.html
Заголовок, (Title) документа по адресу, URL1:
Friedrich Hayek - Wikipedia
Данный printscreen веб страницы (снимок веб страницы, скриншот веб страницы), визуально-программная копия документа расположенного по адресу URL1 и сохраненная в файл, имеет: квалифицированную, усовершенствованную (подтверждены: метки времени, валидность сертификата), открепленную ЭЦП (приложена к данному файлу), что может быть использовано для подтверждения содержания и факта существования документа в этот момент времени. Права на данный скриншот принадлежат администрации Ask3.ru, использование в качестве доказательства только с письменного разрешения правообладателя скриншота. Администрация Ask3.ru не несет ответственности за информацию размещенную на данном скриншоте. Права на прочие зарегистрированные элементы любого права, изображенные на снимках принадлежат их владельцам. Качество перевода предоставляется как есть. Любые претензии, иски не могут быть предъявлены. Если вы не согласны с любым пунктом перечисленным выше, вы не можете использовать данный сайт и информация размещенную на нем (сайте/странице), немедленно покиньте данный сайт. В случае нарушения любого пункта перечисленного выше, штраф 55! (Пятьдесят пять факториал, Денежную единицу (имеющую самостоятельную стоимость) можете выбрать самостоятельно, выплаичвается товарами в течение 7 дней с момента нарушения.)